Switch to: References

Citations of:

An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines

Mind 74 (293):105-116 (1962)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A perception philosophy in Plato.Hugo Filgueiras de Araújo - 2014 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 13:109-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ausland/Sanday Bibliography.Editors Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy - 2013 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 28 (1):36-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Phaedo and Republic V on essences.F. C. White - 1978 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 98:142-156.
    Towards the close of Book V of theRepublicPlato tells us that the true philosopher has knowledge and that the objects of knowledge are the Forms. By contrast, the ‘lovers of sights and sounds’, he tells us, have no more than belief, the objects of which are physical particulars. He then goes on to present us with some very radical-sounding assertions about the nature of these physical particulars. They are bearers of opposite properties, he says, in so thorough-going a manner that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On Essences in the Cratylus.F. C. White - 1978 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):259-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Love and beauty in Plato's "Symposium".F. C. White - 1989 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 109:149-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Anamnesis in the Meno: Part One: The Data of the Theory.Gregory Vlastos - 1965 - Dialogue 4 (2):143-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Analogies of Justice and Health inRepublic IV.Jorge Torres - 2020 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 102 (4):556-587.
    This paper provides a new interpretation of Plato’s account of justice as psychic health in Republic IV. It argues that what has traditionally been considered to be one single analogy is actually a more complex line of reasoning that contains various medical analogies. These medical analogies are not only different in number but also in kind. I discuss each of them separately, while providing a response to various objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Virtues of Unfulfilment: Rethinking Eros and Education in Plato's Symposium.Chien-ya Sun - 2019 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 53 (3):491-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Twelfth-century matter for metaphor: the material view of Plato's Timaeus.Tina Stiefel - 1984 - British Journal for the History of Science 17 (2):169-185.
    Much has been made of Plato's influence of medieval minds, yet as Raymond Klibansky reminds us, much remains to be learned. The twelfth-century Platonist writings are notably various: Brian Stock and Winthrop Weatherbee have examined the effect of Platonic tradition on twelfth-century poetry and Tullio Gregory and Richard Lemay have added to our understanding of its effect on philosophical and theoretical thought in this period. The rich accretions of Hermetic and astrological material have been studied along with the older Plotinian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Truth about Gods and Men.F. E. Sparshott - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (1):3-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Groundwork for Dialectic in Statesman 277a-287b.Colin C. Smith - 2018 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 12 (2):132-150.
    In Plato’s Statesman, the Eleatic Stranger leads Socrates the Younger and their audience through an analysis of the statesman in the service of the interlocutors’ becoming “more capable in dialectic regarding all things”. In this way, the dialectical exercise in the text is both intrinsically and instrumentally valuable, as it yields a philosophically rigorous account of statesmanship and exhibits a method of dialectical inquiry. After the series of bifurcatory divisions in the Sophist and early Statesman, the Stranger changes to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Timaean Particulars.Allan Silverman - 1992 - Classical Quarterly 42 (01):87-.
    At 47e–53c of the Timaeus Plato presents his most detailed metaphysical analysis of particulars. We are told about the construction of the physical universe, the ways we can and cannot talk about the phenomena produced, and about the two causes – Necessity and Intelligence – which govern the processes and results of production. It seems to me that we are told too much and too little: too much, because we have two accounts of the generation of phenomenal particulars – one, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Timaean Particulars.Allan Silverman - 1992 - Classical Quarterly 42 (1):87-113.
    At 47e–53c of the Timaeus Plato presents his most detailed metaphysical analysis of particulars. We are told about the construction of the physical universe, the ways we can and cannot talk about the phenomena produced, and about the two causes – Necessity and Intelligence – which govern the processes and results of production. It seems to me that we are told too much and too little: too much, because we have two accounts of the generation of phenomenal particulars – one, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Antinomies of Plato's Parmenides.Malcolm Schofield - 1977 - Classical Quarterly 27 (1):139-158.
    It is arguable that the student of the deductions which make up the second part of Plato's Parmenides is today better placed than any of his predecessors, save Aristotle, Speusippus, and other immediate associates of Plato, to understand and evaluate those forbidding pages. Ways of looking at and handling the matter of the text are available to him which were not open to those who lived before the rise of critical philological scholarship in Europe in the last century, and of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Penology and Eschatology in Plato's Timaeus and Laws1.T. J. Saunders - 1973 - Classical Quarterly 23 (2):232-244.
    The eschatological myth in the tenth book of the Laws contains a paragraph which purports to explain why, in the next world, efficient treatmentof souls according to their deserts is ‘marvellously easy’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Motion of Intellect On the Neoplatonic Reading of Sophist 248e-249d.Eric D. Perl - 2014 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2):135-160.
    This paper defends Plotinus’ reading ofSophist248e-249d as an expression of the togetherness or unity-in-duality of intellect and intelligible being. Throughout the dialogues Plato consistently presents knowledge as a togetherness of knower and known, expressing this through the myth of recollection and through metaphors of grasping, eating, and sexual union. He indicates that an intelligible paradigm is in the thought that apprehends it, and regularly regards the forms not as extrinsic “objects” but as the contents of living intelligence. A meticulous reading (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Origins of Evil.Jozef Müller - 2020 - Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy 65 (2):179-223.
    The paper addresses the following question: why do human beings, on Aristotle’s view, have an innate tendency to badness, that is, to developing desires that go beyond, and often against, their natural needs? Given Aristotle’s teleological assumptions (including the thesis that nature does nothing in vain), such tendency should not be present. I argue that the culprit is to be found in the workings of rationality. In particular, it is the presence of theoretical reason that necessitates the limitless nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Perception, Relativism, and Truth: Reflections on Plato's Theaetetus 152–160.Mohan Matthen - 1985 - Dialogue 24 (1):33-.
    The standard interpretation of "Theaetetus" 152-160 has Plato attribute to Protagoras a relativistic theory of truth and existence. It is argued here that in fact the individuals of Protagorean worlds are inter-Personal. (thus the Protagorean theory has public objects, but private truth). Also, a new interpretation is offered of Plato's use of heraclitean flux to model relativism. The philosophical and semantic consequences of the interpretation are explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Putting the Cratylus in its Place.Mary Margaret Mackenzie - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (1):124-150.
    The Cratylus begins with a paradox; it ends with a paradox; and it has a paradox in between. But this disturbing characteristic of the dialogue has been overshadowed, not to say ignored, in the literature. For commentators have seen it as their task to discover exactly what theory of language Plato himself, despite his declared perplexity, intends to adopt as he rejects the alternatives of Hermogenes and Cratylus. A common view, then, has been to suppose that the πορίαι of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Plato as a natural scientist.Geoffrey Ernest Richard Lloyd - 1968 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 88:78-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Criteria of fallacy and sophistry for use in the analysis of Platonic dialogues.G. Klosko - 1983 - Classical Quarterly 33 (02):363-.
    In recent years considerable attention has been focused on the question whether Plato ever uses arguments he knows to be sophistical, especially whether he puts such arguments into the mouth of Socrates. Though differing views have been held, at the present time the majority of scholars seem to believe that Plato does not. Though I disagree with this position, I will not attack it directly in this paper. Instead I will discuss what I take to be an important preliminary matter, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Criteria of fallacy and sophistry for use in the analysis of Platonic dialogues.G. Klosko - 1983 - Classical Quarterly 33 (2):363-374.
    In recent years considerable attention has been focused on the question whether Plato ever uses arguments he knows to be sophistical, especially whether he puts such arguments into the mouth of Socrates. Though differing views have been held, at the present time the majority of scholars seem to believe that Plato does not. Though I disagree with this position, I will not attack it directly in this paper. Instead I will discuss what I take to be an important preliminary matter, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Xenophon's Defence of Socrates: The Rhetorical Background to the Socratic Problem.V. J. Gray - 1989 - Classical Quarterly 39 (01):136-.
    The death of Socrates gave birth to an industry of biographical literature which often took the form of a defence or prosecution , sometimes purporting to be the actual defence or prosecution conducted at his trial. Plato and Xenophon wrote works in his defence. Among his critics, one Polycrates had a certain notoriety. Lysias, Theodectes and Demetrius of Phalerum, orators and rhetoricians like Polycrates, were credited with further works of apology. There were doubtless many others. The aim of this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Xenophon's Defence of Socrates: The Rhetorical Background to the Socratic Problem.V. J. Gray - 1989 - Classical Quarterly 39 (1):136-140.
    The death of Socrates gave birth to an industry of biographical literature which often took the form of a defence or prosecution, sometimes purporting to be the actual defence or prosecution conducted at his trial. Plato and Xenophon wrote works in his defence. Among his critics, one Polycrates had a certain notoriety. Lysias, Theodectes and Demetrius of Phalerum, orators and rhetoricians like Polycrates, were credited with further works of apology. There were doubtless many others. The aim of this paper is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and hedonism in Plato's Protagoras.M. Dyson - 1976 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 96:32-45.
    The argument in theProtagoraswhich starts with an analysis of giving in to pleasure in terms of ignorance, and leads into a demonstration that courage is knowledge, is certainly one of the most brilliant in Plato and equally certainly one of the trickiest. My discussion deals mainly with three problems: Precisely what absurdity is detected in the popular account of moral weakness, and where is it located in the text? On the basis of largely formal considerations I believe that the absurdity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Colloquium 9.Deborah De Chiara-Quenzer - 1990 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1):360-370.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is it Wrong to Call Plato A Utilitarian?J. L. Creed - 1978 - Classical Quarterly 28 (02):349-.
    Such is John Stuart Mill's succinct exposition of the core of utilitarian theory. A contemporary philosopher has aptly described utilitarianism as ‘the combination of two principles: the consequentialist principle that the rightness, or wrongness, of an action is determined by the goodness, or badness, of the results that flow from it and the hedonist principle that the only thing that is good in itself is pleasure and the only thing bad in itself is pain. Although the consequentialistprinciple has attracted the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is it Wrong to Call Plato A Utilitarian?J. L. Creed - 1978 - Classical Quarterly 28 (2):349-365.
    Such is John Stuart Mill's succinct exposition of the core of utilitarian theory. A contemporary philosopher has aptly described utilitarianism as ‘the combination of two principles: (1)the consequentialist principlethat the rightness, or wrongness, of an action is determined by the goodness, or badness, of the results that flow from it and (2)the hedonist principlethat the only thing that is good in itself is pleasure and the only thing bad in itself is pain. Although the consequentialistprinciple has attracted the most attention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anamnesis: Platonic Doctrine or Sophistic Absurdity?William S. Cobb - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (4):604-628.
    There are two basic ways in which the phenomenon of learning is explicated in the Platonic dialogues: First, by means of an analogy with vision, and second, by arguing that the acquisition of knowledge is really anamnesis. The analogy with vision is the more common of the two and occurs throughout the dialogues. The passage in the Republic comparing the sun and the good is the best known instance of this approach to the clarification of learning. The basic point of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self‐Motion and Cognition: Plato's Theory of the Soul.Douglas R. Campbell - 2021 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):523-544.
    I argue that Plato believes that the soul must be both the principle of motion and the subject of cognition because it moves things specifically by means of its thoughts. I begin by arguing that the soul moves things by means of such acts as examination and deliberation, and that this view is developed in response to Anaxagoras. I then argue that every kind of soul enjoys a kind of cognition, with even plant souls having a form of Aristotelian discrimination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Plato on the Grammar of Perceiving.M. F. Burnyeat - 1976 - Classical Quarterly 26 (01):29-.
    The question contrasts two ways of expressing the role of the sense organ in perception. In one the expression referring to the sense organ is put into the dative case ; the other is a construction with the preposition δiá governing the genitive case of the word for the sense organ.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Thick Concepts and Moral Revisionism in Plato’s Gorgias: Arguing About Something There Can Be No Argument About.Philipp Brüllmann - 2019 - Phronesis 65 (2):153-178.
    David Furley has suggested that we think of Callicles’ immoralism as attacking a thick concept. I take up this suggestion and apply it to the argument of Plato’s Gorgias more generally. I show that the discussion between Socrates, Gorgias and Polus, which prepares the ground for Callicles, is precisely addressing the thickness of the concept of justice: it reveals that this concept is both descriptive and evaluative and that formulating a revisionist position about justice is therefore extremely difficult. Callicles’ strategy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sobre o argumento “saber ou não-saber” em Teeteto 187d-200c.Anderson De Paula Borges - 2013 - Doispontos 10 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Colloquium 4: The Method of Hypothesis in the Meno.Hugh Benson - 2003 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 18 (1):95-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Departed Souls? Tripartition at the Close of Plato’s Republic.Nathan Bauer - 2017 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 20 (1):139-157.
    Plato’s tripartite soul plays a central role in his account of justice in the Republic. It thus comes as a surprise to find him apparently abandoning this model at the end of the work, when he suggests that the soul, as immortal, must be simple. I propose a way of reconciling these claims, appealing to neglected features of the city-soul analogy and the argument for the soul’s division. The original true soul, I argue, is partitioned, but in a finer manner (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A perception philosophy in Plato.Hugo Filgueiras de Araújo - 2014 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 13:109-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato's Protagoras the Hedonist.Joshua Wilburn - 2016 - Classical Philology 113 (3):224-244.
    I advocate an ad hominem reading of the hedonism that appears in the final argument of the Protagoras. I that attribute hedonism both to the Many and to Protagoras, but my focus is on the latter. I argue that the Protagoras in various ways reflects Plato’s view that the sophist is an inevitable advocate for, and himself implicitly inclined toward, hedonism, and I show that the text aims through that characterization to undermine Protagoras’ status as an educator. One of my (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation