Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. HIV and the right not to know: a reply to replies.Jonathan Youngs & Joshua Simmonds - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):108-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • HIV and the right not to know.Jonathan Youngs & Joshua Simmonds - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):95-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Right Not to Know and the Duty to Tell: The Case of Relatives.Niklas Juth - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):38-52.
    This text is about obtaining and sharing genetic information when there is a potential conflict of interests between patients and their families and relatives. The patient or, in this text, the “index-person,” is someone who is considering obtaining or already has obtained genetic information about herself through genetic testing.The index-person can have several reasons to take an interest in obtaining her genetic information. She may want to know if she has a genetic predisposition for a disorder in order to take (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Right Not to Know and the Duty to Tell: The Case of Relatives.Niklas Juth - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):38-52.
    Obtaining and sharing genetic information when there is a potential conflict of interest between patients and their relatives give rise to two questions. Do we have a duty to find out our genetic predispositions for disease for the sake of our relatives, or do we have a right to remain ignorant? Do we have a duty to disclose our known genetic predispositions for disease to our relatives? I argue that the answer to both questions is yes, but to a lesser (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Incidental findings of uncertain significance: To know or not to know - that is not the question.Bjørn Hofmann - 2016 - BMC Medical Ethics 17 (1):1-9.
    BackgroundAlthough the “right not to know” is well established in international regulations, it has been heavily debated. Ubiquitous results from extended exome and genome analysis have challenged the right not to know. American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics Recommendations urge to inform about incidental findings that pretend to be accurate and actionable. However, ample clinical cases raise the question whether these criteria are met. Many incidental findings are of uncertain significance. The eager to feedback information appears to enter the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Autonomy, the Right Not to Know, and the Right to Know Personal Research Results: What Rights Are There, and Who Should Decide about Exceptions?Gert Helgesson - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):28-37.
    This paper defends the right not to know personal health information, while it discards the right of research participants to receive individual research results. Disagreement regarding the right not to know stems from two different conceptions of autonomy, leading to opposing normative conclusions. Researchers occasionally have good reason to inform research participants about incidental findings in spite of the absence of a right to know such information. Such decisions have to be made by health care personnel and researchers on a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Autonomy, the Right Not to Know, and the Right to Know Personal Research Results: What Rights are There, and Who Should Decide about Exceptions?Gert Helgesson - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (1):28-37.
    Bioethicists have for quite some time discussed the right to know and the right not to know personal health information, such as genetic information acquired in health care and incidental health-related findings in research. Several international ethical guidelines explicitly defend these rights.My own interest in these matters stems from my participation in ethics-related research tied to a longitudinal screening study on Type I diabetes involving young children. A few of the participating parents did not want to be informed if the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Testing the limits of the ‘joint account’ model of genetic information: a legal thought experiment.Charles Foster, Jonathan Herring & Magnus Boyd - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (5):379-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The ethics of non-consensual HIV testing are not substantively different from the ethics of overriding the right not to know a test result.Charles Foster - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):106-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The right not to know and the obligation to know.Ben Davies - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (5):300-303.
    There is significant controversy over whether patients have a ‘right not to know’ information relevant to their health. Some arguments for limiting such a right appeal to potential burdens on others that a patient’s avoidable ignorance might generate. This paper develops this argument by extending it to cases where refusal of relevant information may generate greater demands on a publicly funded healthcare system. In such cases, patients may have an ‘obligation to know’. However, we cannot infer from the fact that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Right Not to Know: some Steps towards a Compromise.Ben Davies & Julian Savulescu - 2020 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 24 (1):137-150.
    There is an ongoing debate in medicine about whether patients have a ‘right not to know’ pertinent medical information, such as diagnoses of life-altering diseases. While this debate has employed various ethical concepts, probably the most widely-used by both defenders and detractors of the right is autonomy. Whereas defenders of the right not to know typically employ a ‘liberty’ conception of autonomy, according to which to be autonomous involves doing what one wants to do, opponents of the right not to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Online consent: how much do we need to know?Bartlomiej Chomanski & Lode Lauwaert - forthcoming - AI and Society:1-11.
    This paper argues, against the prevailing view, that consent to privacy policies that regular internet users usually give is largely unproblematic from the moral point of view. To substantiate this claim, we rely on the idea of the right not to know (RNTK), as developed by bioethicists. Defenders of the RNTK in bioethical literature on informed consent claim that patients generally have the right to refuse medically relevant information. In this article we extend the application of the RNTK to online (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Online consent: how much do we need to know?Bartek Chomanski & Lode Lauwaert - forthcoming - AI and Society.
    This paper argues, against the prevailing view, that consent to privacy policies that regular internet users usually give is largely unproblematic from the moral point of view. To substantiate this claim, we rely on the idea of the right not to know (RNTK), as developed by bioethicists. Defenders of the RNTK in bioethical literature on informed consent claim that patients generally have the right to refuse medically relevant information. In this article we extend the application of the RNTK to online (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark