Switch to: References

Citations of:

Newtonian Studies. By A. Koyré

Philosophy 42 (159):88-90 (1967)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. La metodología de Newton y la demonstración de la realidad de la fuerza.Sebastián Molina Betancur - 2014 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 50:131-154.
    Algunos especialistas de Newton han sostenido que la metodología con la que éste demuestra la existencia de la fuerza se fundamenta en el tratamiento matemático de los fenómenos del movimiento, lo que se ha convertido en la lectura clásica del asunto. No obstante, esta interpretación presenta amplias limitaciones si se examina a la luz de la lectura que intérpretes como Guicciardini y Guerlac proponen. Este artículo muestra las limitaciones de la lectura clásica a la luz de esta lectura más reciente, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Newton’s De gravitatione: a review and reassessment.J. A. Ruffner - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (3):241-264.
    The widely accepted supposition that Newton’s De gravitatione was written in 1684/5 just before composing the Principia is examined. The basis for this determination has serious difficulties starting with the failure to examine the numerical estimates for the resistance of aether. The estimated range is not nearly nil as claimed but comparable with air at or near the earth’s surface. Moreover, the evidence provided most likely stems from experiments by Boyle, Hooke, and others in the 1660s and does not use (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Michael Friedman on Kant and Newton.William Harper - 2000 - Dialogue 39 (2):279-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Has science established that the universe is physically comprehensible?Nicholas Maxwell - 2013 - In Anderson Travena & Brady Soren (eds.), Recent Advances in Cosmology. Nova Science. pp. 1-56.
    Most scientists would hold that science has not established that the cosmos is physically comprehensible – i.e. such that there is some as-yet undiscovered true physical theory of everything that is unified. This is an empirically untestable, or metaphysical thesis. It thus lies beyond the scope of science. Only when physics has formulated a testable unified theory of everything which has been amply corroborated empirically will science be in a position to declare that it has established that the cosmos is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The new science of motion: A study of Galileo's De motu locali.Winifred L. Wisan - 1974 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 13 (2-3):103-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Berkeley, Newton and the stars.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (1):23-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Francis Bacon's “VERULAMIUM” the common‐law template of the modern in english science and culture.Harvey Wheeler - 1999 - Angelaki 4 (1):7 – 26.
    (1999). Francis Bacon's “VERULAMIUM” the common‐law template of the modern in english science and culture. Angelaki: Vol. 4, Judging the law, pp. 7-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphysics and the advancement of science.J. W. N. Watkins - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (2):91-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The aims and method of Kant's 1768 Gegenden im Raume essay in the light of Euler's 1748 Reflexions sur l'espace.David Walford - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (2):305 – 332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Newton's Metaphysics of Space: A “Tertium Quid” Betwixt Substantivalism and Relationism, or merely a “God of the (Rational Mechanical) Gaps”?Edward Slowik - 2009 - Perspectives on Science 17 (4):pp. 429-456.
    This paper investigates the question of, and the degree to which, Newton’s theory of space constitutes a third-way between the traditional substantivalist and relationist ontologies, i.e., that Newton judged that space is neither a type of substance/entity nor purely a relation among such substances. A non-substantivalist reading of Newton has been famously defended by Howard Stein, among others; but, as will be demonstrated, these claims are problematic on various grounds, especially as regards Newton’s alleged rejection of the traditional substance/accident dichotomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Newton’s Neo-Platonic Ontology of Space.Edward Slowik - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (3):419-448.
    This paper investigates Newton’s ontology of space in order to determine its commitment, if any, to both Cambridge neo-Platonism, which posits an incorporeal basis for space, and substantivalism, which regards space as a form of substance or entity. A non-substantivalist interpretation of Newton’s theory has been famously championed by Howard Stein and Robert DiSalle, among others, while both Stein and the early work of J. E. McGuire have downplayed the influence of Cambridge neo-Platonism on various aspects of Newton’s own spatial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The myth of reductive extensionalism.Itay Shani - 2007 - Axiomathes 17 (2):155-183.
    Extensionalism, as I understand it here, is the view that physical reality consists exclusively of extensional entities. On this view, intensional entitities must either be eliminated in favor of an ontology of extensional entities, or be reduced to such an ontology, or otherwise be admitted as non-physical. In this paper I argue that extensionalism is a misguided philosophical doctrine. First, I argue that intensional phenomena are not confined to the realm of language and thought. Rather, the ontology of such phenomena (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Contribution to the Newtonian Scholarship: The “Jesuit Edition” of Isaac Newton’s Principia, a research in progress by Paolo Bussotti and Raffaele Pisano.Rocha Gustavo Rodrigues - 2017 - Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2:242.
    Review of The “Jesuit Edition” of Isaac Newton’s Principia.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Das strukturalistische Problem der theoretischen Begriffe und seine Lösung.Hanspeter Rings - 1987 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 18 (1-2):296-312.
    In especially the Sneed-Stegmüller structuralist theory a so-called problem of theoretical terms emerges. But this problem bases on a questionable presupposition . And the structuralist solution of this problem, the so-called Ramsey-Sneed-solution, is also problematic , , ). Beyond this the structuralist assertion is problematic, that the problem of theoretical terms and his Ramsey-Sneed-solution is empirically relevant . On the basis of the discussed systematic and empirical defects of the problem of theoretical terms and its solution, the so-called non-statement view₂, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conceptual Frameworks on the Relationship Between Physics–Mathematics in the Newton Principia Geneva Edition (1822).Raffaele Pisano & Paolo Bussotti - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (3).
    The aim of this paper is twofold: (1) to show the principal aspects of the way in which Newton conceived his mathematical concepts and methods and applied them to rational mechanics in his Principia; (2) to explain how the editors of the Geneva Edition interpreted, clarified, and made accessible to a broader public Newton’s perfect but often elliptic proofs. Following this line of inquiry, we will explain the successes of Newton’s mechanics, but also the problematic aspects of his perfect geometrical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two Mathematics, Two Gods: Newton and the Second Law.Stuart Pierson - 1994 - Perspectives on Science 2 (2):231-253.
    This article continues the discussion, begun in an earlier contribution to Perspectives on Science, of recent arguments over the coherence of Newton’s physics. The arguments turn on his use of the term “force” in two apparently different ways in the second law. This ambiguity remains because Newton conceived of mathematics in two entirely different ways—the first as a way of describing how things are in themselves, the second as a method of approximation. These two conceptions were, in turn, reflections of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Corpore cadente... : Historians Discuss Newton’s Second Law.Stuart Pierson - 1993 - Perspectives on Science 1 (4):627-658.
    For about the last thirty years Newton scholars have carried on a discussion on the meaning of Newton’s second law and its place in the stucture of his physics. E. J. Dijksterhuis, Brian D. Ellis, R. G. A. Dolby, I. Bernard Cohen, and R. S. Westfall in their treatments of these matters all quote a passage that Newton added to the third edition of the Principia. This passage, beginning “Corpore cadente” (“when a body is falling”), was inserted into the Scholium (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The logic of science and technology as a developmental tendency of modernity.Pietro Daniel Omodeo - 2014 - Thesis Eleven 125 (1):32-48.
    This paper deals with Ágnes Heller’s suggestion, in A Theory of Modernity (1999), to ascribe to science a central role in the ongoing development of modernity. As we shall argue, this is not merely a historical issue but, rather, a historical-philosophical one that entails the problem of defining modernity, science and technology and their mutual interconnections. As for modernity, according to Heller, it is a free developmental project without any foundations other than freedom itself. In particular, the evolution of science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Content of Science Debate in the Historiography of the Scientific Revolution.John Nnaji & José Luis Luján - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):99-109.
    The issue of internalism and externalism in historiography of science was intensely debated two decades ago. The conclusions of such debate on the ‘context of science’ appear to be a reinstatement of the positivist view of the ‘content of science’ as comprising only ideas and concepts uninfluenced by extra-scientific factors. The description of the roles of politics, economy, and socio-cultural factors in science was limited only within the ‘context of science’. This article seeks to resituate the ‘content of science’ debate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Micro-chaos and idealization in cartesian physics.Alan Nelson - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 77 (2-3):377 - 391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Force, Motion, and Leibniz’s Argument from Successiveness.Peter Myrdal - 2021 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103 (4):704-729.
    This essay proposes a new interpretation of a central, and yet overlooked, argument Leibniz offers against Descartes’s power-free ontology of the corporeal world. Appealing to considerations about the successiveness of motion, Leibniz attempts to show that the reality of motion requires force. It is often assumed that the argument is driven by concerns inspired by Zeno. Against such a reading, this essay contends that Leibniz’s argument is instead best understood against the background of an Aristotelian view of the priority of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unification and Revolution: A Paradigm for Paradigms.Nicholas Maxwell - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):133-149.
    Incommensurability was Kuhn’s worst mistake. If it is to be found anywhere in science, it would be in physics. But revolutions in theoretical physics all embody theoretical unification. Far from obliterating the idea that there is a persisting theoretical idea in physics, revolutions do just the opposite: they all actually exemplify the persisting idea of underlying unity. Furthermore, persistent acceptance of unifying theories in physics when empirically more successful disunified rivals can always be concocted means that physics makes a persistent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Quantum propensiton theory: A testable resolution of the wave/particle dilemma.Nicholas Maxwell - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (1):1-50.
    In this paper I put forward a new micro realistic, fundamentally probabilistic, propensiton version of quantum theory. According to this theory, the entities of the quantum domain - electrons, photons, atoms - are neither particles nor fields, but a new kind of fundamentally probabilistic entity, the propensiton - entities which interact with one another probabilistically. This version of quantum theory leaves the Schroedinger equation unchanged, but reinterprets it to specify how propensitons evolve when no probabilistic transitions occur. Probabilisitic transitions occur (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Does probabilism solve the great quantum mystery?Nicholas Maxwell - 2010 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 19 (3):321-336.
    I put forward a micro realistic, probabilistic version of quantum theory, which specifies the precise nature of quantum entities thus solving the quantum wave/particle dilemma, and which both reproduces the empirical success of orthodox quantum theory, and yields predictions that differ from orthodox quantum theory for as yet unperformed experiments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dieu garant de véracité ou Reid critique de Descartes.Louise Marcil-Lacoste - 1975 - Dialogue 14 (4):584-605.
    Récemment, dans The Problem of the Criterion, Roderick M. Chisholm distinguait deux stratégies visant à résoudre le problème du cercle vicieux, à savoir, celle des «particularistes» pour lesquels il faut d'abord établir ce qu'on sait, partant, formuler les criteres de la connaissance et celle des « méthodistes » qui entendent établir d'abord les critères de la connaissance, partant, son étendue. Voici done notre problème formulé, puisque Chisholm considère Descartes comme un exemple de stratégic «méthodiste» et Thomas Reid ainsi que G.E. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Is Newton's Law of Inertia About? Philosophical Reasoning and Explanation in Newton's Principia.Bernd Ludwig - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (1):139-163.
    The ArgumentIn this paper it will be shown that Newton'sPrincipiagives an explication of and an argument for the first Law of Motion, that seems to be outside the scope of today's philosophy of science but was familiar to seventeenth-century commentators: The foundation of classical mechanics is possible only by recurrence to results of a successful technical practice. Laws of classical mechanics gain their meaning as well as their claims to validity only when considered as statements about artifacts whose production belongs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Theories of Scientific Method from Plato to Mach.Laurens Laudan - 1968 - History of Science 7 (1):1-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Spatial ontology and physical modalities.Hugh M. Lacey & Elizabeth Anderson - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 38 (3):261 - 285.
    Most relational theories assert both that spatial discourse is reducible to talk about physical objects and their spatial relations, and that the relation of congruence derives from a non-metrical relation which intervals bear or possibly bear to measuring instruments. We have shown that there are serious logical difficulties involved in maintaining both these positions and the thesis of the continuity of space. We have also shown that Grünbaum's motivating argument for the reduction of congruence is unsound, and, moreover, that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphysics and Natural Philosophy in Descartes and Newton.Andrew Janiak - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (3):403-417.
    This paper compares Newton’s and Descartes’s conceptions of the complex relationship between physics and metaphysics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Newton's Principia from a Logical Point of View.Toshio Ishigaki - 1994 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 8 (4):221-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ¿Qué hace físicamente posible a un mundo posible?Manuel Jesús Herrera Aros & Cristián Ariel López - 2020 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 24 (1):65-88.
    There is a widely extended viewpoint about physical possibility, what we will call Standard Approach, which holds that the physically possible is delimited by the nomological structure of physical theories: to be physically possible is to be in accordance with the physical laws, to be physically impossible is to be prohibited by physical laws and to be physically necessary is to be demanded by the physical laws. However, it is possible to show that this approach is too relaxed and permissive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Michael Friedman on Kant and Newton.William Harper - 2000 - Dialogue 39 (2):279-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the semiotic dimension of ecological theory: The case of island biogeography. [REVIEW]Yrjö Haila - 1986 - Biology and Philosophy 1 (4):377-387.
    The Macarthur-Wilson equilibrium theory of island biogeography has had a contradictory role in ecology. As a lasting contribution, the theory has created a new way of viewing insular environments as dynamical systems. On the other hand, many of the applications of the theory have reduced to mere unimaginative curve-fitting. I analyze this paradox in semiotic terms: the theory was mainly equated with the simple species-area relationship which became a signifier of interesting island ecology. The theory is, however, better viewed as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Beyond the nature-culture dualism.Yrjö Haila - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (2):155-175.
    It is commonly accepted that thewestern view of humanity's place in nature isdominated by a dualistic opposition between nature andculture. Historically this has arisen fromexternalization of nature in both productive andcognitive practices; instances of such externalizationhave become generalized. I think the dualism can bedecomposed by identifying dominant elements in eachparticular instantiation and showing that their strictseparation evaporates under close scrutiny. The philosophical challenge this perspective presents isto substitute concrete socioecological analysis forfoundational metaphysics. A review of majorinterpretations of the history of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Kant’s Asynchronicity Concerning Newtonian Space and Gravity in his Pre-Critical Writings.E. Görg - 2020 - Kantian Journal 39 (4):7-28.
    Kant’s ‘Newtonianism’ has been rightly highlighted by figures like Friedman. The follow-up debates led to a more adequate view on Kant’s natural philosophy and in particular his relation towards Newton. But the discussion that evolved did not point to the asynchronicity that takes place in Kant’s struggle with the central Newtonian concepts. Newtonian space and gravity, in revised form, are of central concern to Kant’s critical philosophy. But Kant adapted and re-evaluated these two concepts in an asynchronous way. While Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Newton’s Use of the Pendulum to Investigate Fluid Resistance: A Case Study and some Implications for Teaching About the Nature of Science.Colin F. Gauld - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (3-4):383-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Empiricism, judgment, and argument; Toward an informal logic of science.MauriceA Finocchiaro - 1988 - Argumentation 2 (3):313-335.
    In an attempt to explore the role of argumentation in scientific inquiry, I explore the conception of argument that appears fruitful in the light of the recent trends in the philosophy of science, away from logical empiricism, and toward a greater emphasis on change, disagreement, and history. I begin by contrasting typical instances philosopers’ theories of both empiricism and apriorism, with typical instances of scientists’ uses of these two attitudes, suggesting that such practice shows a judiciousness lacking in epistemological theory. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Newton and Hooke on Centripetal Force Motion.Herman Erlichson - 1992 - Centaurus 35 (1):46-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Understanding (in) Newton’s Argument for Universal Gravitation.Steffen Ducheyne - 2009 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 40 (2):227-258.
    In this essay, I attempt to assess Henk de Regt and Dennis Dieks recent pragmatic and contextual account of scientific understanding on the basis of an important historical case-study: understanding in Newton’s theory of universal gravitation and Huygens’ reception of universal gravitation. It will be shown that de Regt and Dieks’ Criterion for the Intelligibility of a Theory (CIT), which stipulates that the appropriate combination of scientists’ skills and intelligibility-enhancing theoretical virtues is a condition for scientific understanding, is too strong. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Locke’s Newtonianism and Lockean Newtonianism.Lisa J. Downing - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (3):285-310.
    I explore Locke’s complex attitude toward the natural philosophy of his day by focusing on Locke’s own treatment of Newton’s theory of gravity and the presence of Lockean themes in defenses of Newtonian attraction/gravity by Maupertuis and other early Newtonians. In doing so, I highlight the inadequacy of an unqualified labeling of Locke as “mechanist” or “Newtonian.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Feyerabend's discourse against method: A marxist critique.J. Curthoys & W. Suchting - 1977 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 20 (1-4):243 – 371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Probabilities: Reasonable or true?J. Alberto Coffa - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (2):186-198.
    Hempel's high probability requirement asserts that any rationally acceptable answer to the question 'Why did event X occur?' must offer information which shows that X was to be expected at least with reasonable probability. Salmon rejected this requirement in his S-R model. This led to a series of paradoxical consequences, such as the assertion that an explanation of an event can both lower its probability and make it arbitrarily low, and the assertion that the explanation of an outcome would have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Plausibility of Galileo's Tidal Theory.Martin Clutton-Brock & David Topper - 2011 - Centaurus 53 (3):221-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The human sciences: origins and histories.John Christie - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (1):1-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mathematics as an Instigator of Scientific Revolutions.Stephen G. Brush - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (5-6):495-513.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The disenchanted world and beyond: toward an ecological perspective on science.Michael Ben-Chaim - 1998 - History of the Human Sciences 11 (1):101-127.
    Positivism and, especially, Max Weber's vision of the modern disen chantment of the world are incoherent because they separate human culture from the environment in which human agents pursue their life- projects. The same problem is manifested, more blatantly, in current social studies of science, which take the project of disenchantment further by disenchanting science itself. A different image of science is traced to classical empiricism, whose paradigm of learning is belief and, more specifically, the practical nature of the believer's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz and Newton on Space.Ori Belkind - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (3):467-497.
    This paper reexamines the historical debate between Leibniz and Newton on the nature of space. According to the traditional reading, Leibniz (in his correspondence with Clarke) produced metaphysical arguments (relying on the Principle of Sufficient Reason and the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles) in favor of a relational account of space. Newton, according to the traditional account, refuted the metaphysical arguments with the help of an empirical argument based on the bucket experiment. The paper claims that Leibniz’s and Newton’s arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kepler's Laws of Planetary Motion, Before and After Newton's "Principia": an Essay on the Transformation of Scientific Problems.Brian S. Baigrie - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (2):177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Karl Popper, Science and Enlightenment.Nicholas Maxwell - 2017 - London: UCL Press.
    Karl Popper is famous for having proposed that science advances by a process of conjecture and refutation. He is also famous for defending the open society against what he saw as its arch enemies – Plato and Marx. Popper’s contributions to thought are of profound importance, but they are not the last word on the subject. They need to be improved. My concern in this book is to spell out what is of greatest importance in Popper’s work, what its failings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From Darwin to Watson and Back Again: The Principle of Animal-Environment Mutuality.Alan Costall - 2004 - Behavior and Philosophy 32 (1):179-195.
    Modern cognitive psychology presents itself as the revolutionary alternative to behaviorism, yet there are blatant continuities between modern cognitivism and the mechanistic kind of behaviorism that cognitivists have in mind, such as their commitment to methodological behaviorism, the stimulus–response schema, and the hypothetico-deductive method. Both mechanistic behaviorism and cognitive behaviorism remain trapped within the dualisms created by the traditional ontology of physical science—dualisms that, one way or another, exclude us from the "physical world." Darwinian theory, however, put us back into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations