Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kant the Naturalist.Robert B. Louden - 2020 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (1):3-17.
    Kant is widely admired – and sometimes also widely criticized – as the founding father of transcendental philosophy. But in much of my own writing, I have been concerned with a very different Kant: an impure rather than a pure Kant, an a posteriori rather than an a priori Kant, a naturalistic rather than a transcendental Kant. This other Kant has often been overlooked by professional philosophers, and when not overlooked, he is often regarded as shallow and unoriginal. My aim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Total Transformation’: Why Kant Did Not Give up on Education.Robert B. Louden - 2016 - Kantian Review 21 (3):393-413.
    In this essay I argue that Kant remained committed to the necessity and fundamental importance of education throughout his career. Like Johann Bernhard Basedow (1724–90), Kant holds that a ‘total transformation’ of schools is necessary, and he holds this view not only in the 1770s but in his later years as well. In building my case I try to refute two recent opposing interpretations – Reinhard Brandt’s position that Kant’s early ‘education enthusiasm’ was later replaced by a politics enthusiasm, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Establishment Of The Standard History Ofphilosophy of Education and Suppressed Traditions of Education.Daniel Tröhler - 2004 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 23 (5):367-391.
    History of education emerges during the course of the nineteenth century in Germany and is marked by four features. It is educational, and not scientific in nature, because it was written primarily for teacher education and training; it is national, or even nationalistic; it is oriented almost exclusively towards German philosophy; and it is indebted to Lutheran Protestantism. This model of pedagogical historiography leaves its mark on the historiographies that emerged later in England, France, and the United States. Taking the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From phrenology to the laboratory.Tom Quick - 2014 - History of the Human Sciences 27 (5):54-73.
    The claim that mind is an epiphenomenon of the nervous system became academically respectable during the 19th century. The same period saw the establishment of an ideal of science as institutionalized endeavour conducted in laboratories. This article identifies three ways in which the ‘physiological psychology’ movement in Britain contributed to the latter process: first, via an appeal to the authority of difficult-to-access sites in the analysis of nerves; second, through the constitution of a discourse internal to it that privileged epistemology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction: Do We Have Good Reasons to Commemorate Rousseau in 2012? [REVIEW]Daniel Tröhler - 2012 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 31 (5):431-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brain science and the human spirit.Colwyn Trevarthen - 1986 - Zygon 21 (2):161-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations