Skip to main content
Log in

Language of Thought: The Connectionist Contribution

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Fodor and Pylyshyn's critique of connectionism has posed a challenge to connectionists: Adequately explain such nomological regularities as systematicity and productivity without postulating a "language of thought" (LOT). Some connectionists like Smolensky took the challenge very seriously, and attempted to meet it by developing models that were supposed to be non-classical. At the core of these attempts lies the claim that connectionist models can provide a representational system with a combinatorial syntax and processes sensitive to syntactic structure. They are not implementation models because, it is claimed, the way they obtain syntax and structure sensitivity is not "concatenative," hence "radically different" from the way classicists handle them. In this paper, I offer an analysis of what it is to physically satisfy/realize a formal system. In this context, I examine the minimal truth-conditions of LOT Hypothesis. From my analysis it will follow that concatenative realization of formal systems is irrelevant to LOTH since the very notion of LOT is indifferent to such an implementation level issue as concatenation. I will conclude that to the extent to which they can explain the law-like cognitive regularities, a certain class of connectionist models proposed as radical alternatives to the classical LOT paradigm will in fact turn out to be LOT models, even though new and potentially very exciting ones.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aydede, Murat (1995a), “What Is Wrong with the Syntactic Theory of Minds,” MS., The University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, Murat (1995b), “Typing Mentalese Tokens: Fodor's Dilemma,” MS., The University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Keith (1991), “Towards a Connectionist Cognitive Architecture,” Mind and Language6, No. 3, pp. 252–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David (1990), “Syntactic Transformations on Distributed Representations,” Connection Science2, pp. 53–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David (1991), “Why Fodor and Pylyshyn Were Wrong: The Simplest Refutation,” in Proceedings of the l2th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, pp. 340–7.

  • Cummins, Robert (1989), Meaning and Mental Representation, Cambridge,Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, Robert and Georg Schwarz (1991), “Connectionism, Computation, and Cognition,” in Terence Horgan and John Tienson, eds., Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, Studies in Cognitive Systems (Volume 9), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald (1980), “Freedom to Act,” Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Martin (1991), “Concepts, Connectionism, and the Language of Thought,” inW. Ramsey, S.P. Stich and D.E. Rumelhart, eds., Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, Michael (1990), “A Narrow Representational Theory of the Mind,” InW.G. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, Michael (1996), Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, Jeffrey L. (1989), “Structured Representations and Connectionist Models,” in Proceedings of the Eleventh Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Ann Arbor, Michigan, pp. 17–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1975), The Language of Thought, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1980), “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology,” RePresentations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1981. (Originally appeared in Behaviorial and Brain Sciences3, 1, 1980.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1985), “Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation,” A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1991), “Replies” (Ch.15), in B. Loewer and G. Rey eds., Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. and Zenon W. Pylyshyn (1988), “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis,” in S. Pinker and J. Mehler, eds., Connections and Symbols, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press (A Cognition Special Issue).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. and B. McLaughlin (1990), “Connectionism and the Problem of Systematicity: Why Smolensky's Solution Doesn't Work,” Cognition35, pp. 183–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goel, Vinod (1991), “Notationality and the Information Processing Mind,” Minds and Machines1, pp. 129–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, John (1982), “Analog and Analog,” in J.I. Biro and R.W. Shahan, eds., Mind, Brain and Function, Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, John (1985), Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson (1976), The Languages of Art, Second Edition, Indianapolis, Hackett.

  • Hinton, Geoffrey (1990), “Mapping Part-Whole Hierarchies into Connectionist Network,” Artificial Intelligence46, Nos. 1–2 (Special Issue on Connectionist Symbol Processing).

    Google Scholar 

  • St. John, M.F. and J.L. McClelland (1990), “Learning and Applying Contextual Constraints in Sentence Comprehension,” Artificial Intelligence46, Nos. 1- 2 (Special Issue on Connectionist Symbol Processing).

  • Loewer, Barry and Georges Rey (eds.), (1990), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, William (1993), “A Deductive Argument for the Representational Theory of Thinking,” Mind and Language, Vol. 8, No. 3, pp. 404–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B.P. (1993a), “The Connectionism/Classicism Battle to Win Souls,” Philosophical Studies71, pp. 163–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B.P. (1993b), “Systematicity, Conceptual Truth, and Evolution”, in C. Hookway and D. Peterson, eds., Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Royal Institute of Philosophy, Supplement No. 34.

  • Minsky, M. (1967), Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollack, J.B. (1990), “Recursive Distributed Representations”, Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 46, Nos. 1- 2 (Special Issue on Connectionist Symbol Processing), November 1990.

  • Putnam, Hilary (1988), Representation and Reality, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, ZenonW. (1984), Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, Georges (1991), “An Explanatory Budget for Connectionism and Eliminativism,” in T. Horgan and J. Tienson, eds., Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, Georges (1995), “A Not “Merely Empirical” Argument for a Language of Thought” in J. Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives9, pp. 201–222.

  • Searle, John R. (1984), Minds, Brains and Science, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, Paul (1988), “On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences11, pp. 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, Paul (1990a), “Connectionism, Constituency, and the Language of Thought,” in B. Loewer and G. Rey, eds., Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, Paul (1990b), “Tensor Product Variable Binding and the Representation of Symbolic Structures in Connectionist Systems,” Artificial Intelligence, Vo1. 46, Nos. 1- 2 (Special Issue on Connectionist Symbol Processing), November 1990.

  • Smolensky, Paul (1995), “Reply: Constituent Structure and Explanation in an Integrated Connectionist/ Symbolic Cognitive Architecture,” in Cynthia and Graham Macdonald, eds., Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, Stephen P. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R.H. (1969), Symbolic Logic, New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, Timothy (1990), “Compositionality: A Connectionist Variation on a Classical Theme,” Cognitive Science, Vo1. 14, pp. 355–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, Timothy (1991), “Classical Questions,Radical Answers:Connectionism and the Structure of Mental Representations,” in Terence Horgan and John Tienson, eds., Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, Studies in Cognitive Systems (Volume 9), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aydede, M. Language of Thought: The Connectionist Contribution. Minds and Machines 7, 57–101 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008203301671

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008203301671

Navigation