Skip to main content
Log in

Morgan’s Canon, meet Hume’s Dictum: avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How should we determine the distribution of psychological traits—such as Theory of Mind, episodic memory, and metacognition—throughout the Animal kingdom? Researchers have long worried about the distorting effects of anthropomorphic bias on this comparative project. A purported corrective against this bias was offered as a cornerstone of comparative psychology by C. Lloyd Morgan in his famous “Canon”. Also dangerous, however, is a distinct bias that loads the deck against animal mentality: our tendency to tie the competence criteria for cognitive capacities to an exaggerated sense of typical human performance. I dub this error “anthropofabulation”, since it combines anthropocentrism with confabulation about our own prowess. Anthropofabulation has long distorted the debate about animal minds, but it is a bias that has been little discussed and against which the Canon provides no protection. Luckily, there is a venerable corrective against anthropofabulation: a principle offered long ago by David Hume, which I call “Hume’s Dictum”. In this paper, I argue that Hume’s Dictum deserves a privileged place next to Morgan’s Canon in the methodology of comparative psychology, illustrating my point through a discussion of the debate over Theory of Mind in nonhuman animals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In practice, many comparative psychologists read the Canon in a stronger way, as recommending the default position that animal behavior is driven by lower processes unless evidence can be provided that only explanation in terms of higher processes is adequate. On the weaker reading adopted throughout this article, we should instead remain agnostic about results that could be explained by either higher or lower causes. I do not here explore the question as to which interpretation was intended by Morgan (for that see Richards (1989) and Radick (2000), who reach somewhat different conclusions).

  2. This vagueness could be either epistemic or metaphysical. If the disputed terms are natural kind terms, for instance, then they may really have sharp boundaries, and borderline cases are a temporary product of our ignorance of these kinds’ underlying natures. Alternatively, if defining a term requires ineliminable appeal to evaluatives—like “reliable” or “intelligent”—then vagueness may be a permanent feature of its associated concept.

  3. Listing these proponents together is not meant to suggest that there are not subtle differences amongst their positions—only that they share a common thread, denied by Povinelli and colleagues, that existing data from experiments on competitive situations alone provides good evidence that some non-human primates have a perceptual ToM.

  4. As degree of representational reliability is a robust source of vagueness, it is likely that the treatment of this section could be extended to debates over the possession by animals of other capacities characterized in terms of representational contents—including at least metacognition (similarly described as the ability to represent one’s own mental states) and episodic memory (often characterized in terms of the “what-when-where” information recorded in an episodic memory).

  5. Note that we should distinguish skepticism about whether a given experiment is powerful enough to assess some criterion from skepticism about whether animals possess the psychological ability the criterion was elected to assess. For example, Carruthers may be right that existing animal metacognition experiments can be explained in terms of first-order mechanisms, but wrong that this prevents these experiments from providing evidence that animals possess “genuine” metacognition (because this assumption rests on an inflated criterion for metacognition).

  6. Though I will not explore the implications here, semantic anthropocentrism and confabulation about human performance could also be combined with anthropomorphism. This triumvirate of biases would result in the worst outcome yet: a comparative methodology which both presumed an inflated account of some psychological capacity and attributed that inflated capacity to animals on the basis of insufficient evidence. While I suspect this kind of triple error is the mistake that Penn and Povinelli take their critical targets to have committed, this case falls apart if proponents do not share in their semantic anthropocentrism.

  7. The sense in which anthropofabulation is implicit or automatic requires some elaboration. Often, both errors that comprise anthropofabulation will be tacit—anthropofabulists will implicitly confabulate about the complexity of their own performance and implicitly presume that only similarly complex performance is worthy of the name. Penn and Povinelli, however, repeatedly complain that our understanding of ToM has relied too much on what they call “our species' inveterate intuitions about how our own ToM works” (2007, 732), so they cannot be accused of committing the former error unawares. However, there is little evidence that they have critically evaluated the latter semantic assumption that “genuine” ToM requires the kind of domain-general competence presumed by this inflated folk psychology.

  8. For a related discussion of comparisons between taxonomies, see Griffiths (1999, 216–219); and for an in-depth discussion of explanatory power, see Ylikoski and Kuorikoski (2010).

  9. Whiten’s “intervening variable” notion does require the integration of information across some range of perceptually disparate situations to justify the appeal to a hidden variable. However, Call and Tomasello (2008) contend that existing experiments already demonstrate that chimpanzees respond appropriately to the mental states of others across a variety of perceptually disparate situations by integrating a complex combination of cues, including eye-directions, body orientations, whether the line of gaze does or does not terminate in a plausible target, presence or absence of occluders, and the type of occluders involved.

  10. This is not to say that consensus stereotypes cannot change over time. For example, if we learned that the association between autism and ToM-deficits were a statistical artifact, or that ‘autism’ conflates distinct disorders with different etiologies, we might revise our stereotype to modify or exclude property 3.

  11. While the former, definitional form of anthropofabulation is more methodologically troublesome (because it semantically institutionalizes bias), the latter is also a serious and closely-related form of error that can similarly be avoided by attending to Hume’s Dictum.

  12. Unless, of course, verbal acuity is an essential component of the capacity being assessed.

  13. For a brief discussion on how compositional operators can support the accommodation of abstract taxonomies to underlying diversity, see Boyd (1999, 157–158). Note that differences in degree captured by such modifiers may or may not indicate qualitative differences; for example, the two architecturally distinct systems for human ToM postulated by Apperly and Butterfill (2009) might be mapped to ms+ and ms++, respectively.

  14. Indeed, a reviewer points out that Morgan himself would likely have been sympathetic to Hume’s position here. Morgan was well-aware that humans often overestimate their own prowess and that this can interfere with cross-species comparisons—warning that “to interpret animal behavior one must learn also to see one's own mentality at levels of development much lower than one's top-level of reflective self-consciousness. It is not easy, and savors somewhat of paradox" (Morgan 1930, 250).

References

  • Andrews K (2005) Chimpanzee theory of mind: looking in all the wrong places? Mind Lang 20(5):521–536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews K (2012) Do apes read minds? Toward a new folk psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly I, Buterfill S (2009) Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychol Rev 116:953–970

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariely D (2009) Predictably irrational: the hidden forces that shape our decisions. Harper Collins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariely D (2012) The (honest) truth about dishonesty: how we lie to everyone–especially ourselves. Harper Collins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett L (2008) Out of their heads: turning relational reinterpretation inside out. Behav Brain Sci 31(2):130–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez JL (2003) The domain of folk psychology. In: O’Hear A (ed) Minds and persons. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Boesch C (2007) What makes us human (Homo sapiens)? The challenge of cognitive cross-species comparison. J Comp Psychol 121(3):227–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner C (2013) The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mindreading. Mind Lang

  • Buckner R, Carroll D (2007) Self-projection and the brain. Trends Cogn Sci 11(2):49–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bugnyar T (2007) An integrative approach to the study of “theory-of-mind”-like abilities in ravens. Jpn J Anim Psychol 57(1):15–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bulloch M, Boysen S, Furlong E (2008) Visual attention and its relation to knowledge states in chimpanzees, Pan troglodytes. Anim Behav 76(4):1147–1155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call J, Tomasello M (2008) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends Cogn Sci 12(5):187–192. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2008.02.010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2008) Meta-cognition in animals: a skeptical look. Mind Lang 23(1):58–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2009) How we know our own minds: the relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behav Brain Sci 32(2):121–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal F (2000) Anthropomorphism and anthropodenial: consistency in our thinking about humans and other animals. Philos Top 27:255–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1986) Misrepresentation. In: Bogan R (ed) Belief: form, content and function. New York, Oxford, pp 17–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior: reasons in a world of causes. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Emery NJ, Clayton NS (2009) Comparative social cognition. Annu Rev Psychol 60(1):87–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick S (2008) Doing away with Morgan’s canon. Mind Lang 23(2):224–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick S (2009) The primate mindreading controversy: a case study in simplicity and methodology in animal psychology. In: Lurz R (ed) The philosophy of animal minds. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 258–277

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher L, Carruthers P (2012) Behavior–reading versus mentalizing in animals. In: Metcalfe J, Terrace H (eds) Agency and Joint attention. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Flombaum JI, Santos LR (2005) Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Curr Biol 15(5):447–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Povinelli D (2012) Enactive and behavioral abstraction accounts of social understanding in chimpanzees, infants, and adults. Rev Philos Psychol 3:145–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (2002) Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgement. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 208–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes C (1998) Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behav Brain Sci 21:101–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739) A treatise on human nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeley B (2004) Anthropomorphism, primatomorphism, mammalomorphism: understanding cross-species comparisons. Biol Philos 19:521–540

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz R (2009) If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philos Psychol 22(3):305–328. doi:10.1080/09515080902970673

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz R (2011) Mindreading animals: the debate over what animals know about other minds. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Macmillan N (2002) Signal detection theory. In: Yantis S (ed) Stevens’ handbook of experimental psychology. Coughlan Publishing, Mankato

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle B (2011) Time to give up the dogmas of attribution: an alternative theory of behavior explanation. In: Zanna M (ed) Advances in experimental social psychology. Academic Press, Salt Lake City

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle B, Knobe J, Nelson S (2007) Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: new answers to an old question. J Pers Soc Psychol 93(4):491–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGonigle B, Chalmers M (2008) Putting Descartes before the horse (again!). Behav Brain Sci 32(2):142–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan CL (1903) An introduction to comparative psychology. In: Scott W (ed), p 386

  • Morgan CL (1930) Autobiography of C. Lloyd Morgan. In: Murchison C (ed) History of psychology in autobiography, vol 2. Clark University Press, Worcester, MA, pp 237–264

  • Nisbett R, Ross L (1980) Human inference: strategies and shortcomings of social judgment. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett R, Ross L (1991) The person and the situation. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett R, Wilson T (1977) Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychol Rev 84(3):231–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penn D, Povinelli D (2007) On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a theory of mind. Philos Trans R Soc Lond Ser B Biol Sci 362(1480):731–744

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penn D, Povinelli D (2013) The comparative delusion: the behaviorstic/mentalistic dichotomy in comparative theory of mind research. Terrace HA, Metcalfe J (eds) Agency and joint attention, Oxford University Press

  • Penn D, Holyoak K, Povinelli D (2008) Darwin’s mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. In: Smith B, Woodruff Smith D (eds) Behav Brain Sci, 31(2): 109–130; discussion 130–178

  • Piolino P, Hisland M, Ruffeveille I, Matuszewski V, Jambaque I, Eustache F (2007) Do school-age children remember or know the personal past? Conscious Cogn 16(2007):84–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli D (2004) Behind the ape’s appearance: escaping anthropocentrism in the study of other minds. Daedalus 133(1):29–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli D (2011) World without weight: perspectives on an alien mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli D, Eddy T (1996) What young chimpanzees know about seeing. Monogr Soc Res Child Dev 61(3):1–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli D, Vonk J (2003) Chimpanzee minds: suspiciously human? Trends Cogn Sci 7(4):157–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli D, Vonk J (2004) We don’t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee’s mind. Mind Lang 19(1):1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack D, Woodruff G (1978) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behav Brain Sci 1(04):515–526. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00076512

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radick G (2000) Morgan’s canon, Garner’s phonograph, and the evolutionary origins of language and reason. Br J Hist Sci 33(1):3–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards R (1989) Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos L, Flombaum J, Phillips W (2007) The evolution of human mindreading: how non-human primates can inform social cognitive neuroscience. In: Platek S, Keenan J, Shackleford T (eds) Evolutionary cognitive neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 433–456

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter D (1999) The seven sins of memory: insights from psychology and cognitive neuroscience. Am Psychol 54(3):182–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnider A (2008) The confabulating mind: how the brain creates reality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth S (2009) The evolution of comparative cognition: is the snark still a boojum? Behav Process 80(3):210–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons D, Chabris C (2011) What people believe about how memory works: a representative survey of the US population. PLoS ONE 6(8):e22757

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1998) Morgan’s canon. In: Cummins D, Allen C (eds) The evolution of mind. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 224–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2005) Comparative psychology meets evolutionary biology: Morgan’s canon and cladistic parsimony. In: Dalston L, Mitman G (eds) Thinking with animals: new perspectives on anthropomorphism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf T, Corballis M (2008) New evidence for animal foresight? Anim Behav 75(5):e1–e3. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2008.01.006

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas R (2006) Lloyd Morgan’s Canon: a history of misrepresentation. Hist Theory Psychol Epr Arch

  • Tomasello M, Call J (2006) Do chimpanzees know what others see—or only what they are looking at? In: Hurley S, Nudds M (eds) Rational animals? Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Tomasello M, Call J, Hare B (2003) Chimpanzees versus humans: it’s not that simple. Trends Cogn Sci 7(8):239–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving E (1985) Memory and consciousness. Can Psychol 26(1):1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science 185(4157):1124–1131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Hippel W, Trivers R (2011) The evolution and psychology of self-deception. Behav Brain Sci 34(1):1–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynne C (2007) What are animals? Why anthropomorphism is still not a scientific approach to behavior. Comp Cogn Behav Rev 2:125–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski P, Kuorikoski J (2010) Dissecting explanatory power. Philos Stud 148(2):201–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Colin Allen, Louise Barrett, Melinda Fagan, Anika Fiebich, Daniel Povinelli, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and discussion. The essay also benefitted from discussions on an early version presented at the 2011 Winter Conference on Animal Learning & Behavior. Finally, I thank the Alexander von Humboldt Stiftung for the postdoctoral fellowship that partially supported this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cameron Buckner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Buckner, C. Morgan’s Canon, meet Hume’s Dictum: avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons. Biol Philos 28, 853–871 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9376-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9376-0

Keywords

Navigation