Skip to main content
Log in

The great beetle debate: a study in imagining with names

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

Statements about fictional characters, such as “Gregor Samsa has been changed into a beetle,” pose the problem of how we can say something true (or false) using empty names. I propose an original solution to this problem that construes such utterances as reports of the “prescriptions to imagine” generated by works of fiction. In particular, I argue that we should construe these utterances as specifying, not what we are supposed to imagine—the propositional object of the imagining—but how we are supposed to imagine. Most other theories of thought and discourse about fictional characters either fail to capture the intentionality of our imaginings, or else obscure the differences between imaginings directed toward fictional characters and those directed toward real individuals. I argue that once we have an account of prescriptions to imagine about real individuals, we can adapt the same framework to specify the contents of prescriptions to imagine about fictional characters, and thereby to account for the truth (or falsity) of statements about fictional characters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On some accounts such statements cannot be true or false, but only correct or incorrect; I address this below.

  2. In fact Eagle’s account of correctness conditions appears similar to my proposal, though it is not developed in detail.

  3. Though Braun (2005) argues that gappy propositions are just false.

  4. Hanley (2004) argues that Lewis should use the method of intersection to deal with many of these cases and, where the method of intersection fails, we need not necessarily accept a contradiction just because it is in the text. Even if Hanley’s defense of Lewis is sufficient—and I am skeptical—I think Walton’s approach is to be preferred, both because it captures the central role of imagining in response to fictions and because it applies to a wider range of fictional discourse (as discussed below). Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.

  5. This does not mean that we are obligated to imagine everything that is fictionally true. To say that it is fictionally true that Anna Karenina needs oxygen is just to say that if the question arises—which it usually doesn’t—and we have to decide between imagining that Anna needs oxygen and imagining that she does not, we should imagine the former (Walton 1990, p. 40).

  6. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

  7. This is merely an assumption. While Nabokov makes a good argument, there is no fact of the matter whether we are supposed to imagine that Gregor becomes a beetle or any other kind of vermin. This indeterminacy does not indicate anything mysterious about the nature of fictional characters, but is rather a result of the fact that there is a limit to the amount of information a work of fiction gives us in prescribing imaginings.

  8. Not all languages translate the Greek and Latin names for this character differently, and this is one reason to think that the English names co-identify. But the justification of any claims about reference in works of fiction must appeal to the interpretation of those works. I would defend the identity of the character between Homer’s Iliad and Dante’s Inferno, for example, by arguing that one could not properly understand the latter without recognizing the character as Homer’s.

  9. There are differences among these theories. One view is that the names of fictional characters function as variables in existentially quantified sentences prefixed by a fictionality operator; the name’s semantic contribution consists in all the predicates associated with it in the fiction (Kaplan 1973; Currie 1990). An alternative view is that a name appearing within the scope of a fictionality operator refers to its “customary sense,” which is given by the core of salient properties associated with the name (Lamarque and Olsen 1994). My objections are meant to apply to both approaches.

  10. For more detailed criticisms of realism, see Everett (2005) and Friend (2007).

  11. As Walton has pointed out to me, the solution I offer below can be construed as a way of individuating kinds of pretense within the constraints of his account.

  12. See Braun (1993) for an argument in favor of the latter (which he there calls the ‘unfilled proposition’ view) over the former. For further development of the gappy proposition view, see also Adams et al. (1997), Braun (2005) and the articles cited in the next note.

  13. Adams and Stecker (1994), Taylor (2000) and Adams and Dietrich (2004) defend versions of this view. See Reimer (2001), Everett (2003) and Green (2007) for criticisms.

  14. Adams and Dietrich (2004) also invoke the “causal history of the name” (p. 128ff) to fill out the pragmatic portion of the gappy proposition view, but do not develop the idea in detail.

  15. While it makes a difference that we represent contents with structured propositions (rather than possible worlds), nothing in my argument depends on how these propositions are construed. I take propositions to be nothing more than a way of representing truth conditions.

  16. This claim purposely leaves open the possibility that in other fictions in which the name ‘London’ is used, our interpretation of the work would lead us to conclude that there is no reference to the real city.

  17. As Anthony Everett has pointed out to me, there could be fictions that require us to imagine about real individuals under distinct modes of presentation, for instance a story in which “Chomsky the linguist” and “Chomsky the political activist” are two different people. I take it that such stories are rare, though they do deserve fuller discussion than I can offer here.

  18. Ian Proops drew this to my attention.

  19. The assumption that propositional attitudes can be understood as involving structured mental representations is not uncontroversial, but in my view it is the best explanation of many features of propositional attitudes; see, e.g., Fodor (1987, 1990). Further, research on narrative comprehension in cognitive psychology and linguistics supports the hypothesis that we create and update mental representations of characters while reading (see, e.g., the papers in Goldman et al. 1999). I say nothing here about the relations that constitute attitude-types, such as imagining, believing, desiring, etc., though I assume they are distinguished functionally.

  20. I owe this terminology to Ian Proops (in conversation).

  21. This terminology is introduced in Crimmins and Perry (1989).

  22. The term dossier originates in Grice (1969).

  23. We can, of course, have notions that are not labeled with names, including notions of fictional characters. In these cases we usually appeal to a description as a way of accessing information stored in memory.

  24. This is not to say that the psychological mode of presentation is identical to the (linguistic) character (see Recanati 1993, p. 69ff). The distinction is not important for present purposes, however, so long as there is a systematic correspondence.

  25. I take the term ‘root’ from Perry’s unpublished “Saying Nothing?” (1997).

  26. If it is possible to refer to abstract objects that lack causal powers, we should doubt that this relation can be reduced to purely causal connections; but the basic idea of notion networks does not assume any such reduction.

  27. A theory need not assume referentialism about names to invoke something like notion networks (see, e.g., Sainsbury 2005).

  28. It is possible that there be more than one notion network rooted in a real individual. I address this issue below. For now I assume that Pierre, Frank, etc., participate in only one network.

  29. More needs to be said about how to distinguish different “branches” of notion networks (see Everett 2000). One other advantage of appealing to segments of notion networks is that they help explain cases in which our intuitions about identification diverge. For instance, we typically identify Superman and Clark Kent but there are (Frege-style) contexts in which we might not. We typically identify Odysseus/Ulysses as the same character in Homer, Virgil, and Dante; but sometimes it is useful to speak of distinct characters. The contrasts can be explained by appealing to the whole network or to different branches. (Thanks to an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this point.).

  30. To say that the convention was instituted in the story is a simplification, since Kafka would have come up with the name and the character beforehand, for example in working the story out in rough drafts. I ignore this complication here.

  31. Perry offers a brief account of fictional discourse (Perry 2001, pp. 170–172), but it differs from mine in several respects.

  32. Thanks to Jason Stanley.

  33. I owe this suggestion and its elaboration to Anthony Everett.

  34. John Perry suggested this line of argument.

  35. For example, one could argue that “Gregor Samsa is a fictional character” is true so long as (very roughly) (i) the Gregor-network originates in a fiction, and (ii) that fiction prescribes imagining that the network has a root.

  36. Thanks to an anonymous referee for emphasizing these further applications.

References

  • Adams, F., & Dietrich, L. (2004). What’s in a(n empty) name? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85, 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., Fuller, G., & Stecker, R. (1997). The semantics of fictional names. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78, 128–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Stecker, R. (1994). Vacuous singular terms. Mind & Language, 9, 387–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (1993). Empty names. Noûs, 27, 449–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2005). Empty names, fictional names, mythical names. Noûs, 39, 596–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvino, I. (1993). If on a winter’s night a traveler. New York: Everyman’s Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1966). ‘He’: A study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio, 8, 130–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crimmins, M., & Perry, J. (1989). The prince and the phone booth: Reporting puzzling beliefs. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 685–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1990). The nature of fiction. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1968). On saying that. Synthèse, 19, 130–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donellan, K. (1974). Speaking of nothing. Philosophical Review, 83, 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eagle, A. (2007). Telling tales. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107, 125–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1973). The causal theory of names. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 47, 187–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2000). Referentialism and empty names. In A. Everett & T. Hofweber (Eds.), Empty names, fiction and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 37–60). Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2003). Empty names and ‘gappy’ propositions. Philosophical Studies, 116, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2005). Against fictional realism. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 624–649.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (ms). Empty names, fiction, pretense, and existence.

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1997). Letter to Phillip Jourdain, Jan. 1914. In M. Beaney (Ed.), The Frege Reader (pp. 319–322). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friend, S. (2007). Fictional characters. Philosophy Compass, 2, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, S. R., Graesser, A. C., & van den Broek, P. (Eds.). (1999). Narrative comprehension, causality, and coherence. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. (2007). Direct reference, empty names, and implicature. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 37, 419–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1969). Vacuous names. In D. Davidson & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Words and objections (pp. 118–145). Dordrecht/Holland: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanley, R. (2004). As good as it gets: Lewis on truth in fiction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 112–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. (1979). Fictional objects: How they are and how they aren’t. Poetics, 8, 129–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1973). Bob and Carol and Ted and Alice. In J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 490–518). Dordrecht/Holland: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (2000). Negative existentials. In A. Everett & T. Hofweber (Eds.), Empty names, fiction and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 95–116). Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, P., & Olsen, S. H. (1994). Truth, fiction, and literature: A philosophical perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). Truth in fiction. In Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 261–280). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Nabokov, V. (1980). Franz Kafka: The Metamorphosis. In F. Bowers (Ed.), Lectures on literature. San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwell, G. (1962). Nineteen eighty-four. New York: New American Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1990). Self-notions. Logos, 11, 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Reference and reflexivity. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1993). Direct reference: From language to thought. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2000). Oratio recta, oratio obliqua: An essay on metarepresentation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (2001). The problem of empty names. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79, 491–506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riffaterre, M. (1990). Fictional truth. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R. M. (2005). Reference without referents. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, K. A. (2000). Emptiness without compromise. In A. Everett & T. Hofweber (Eds.), Empty names, fiction and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 17–36). Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellek, R., & Warren, A. (1956). Theory of literature (3rd ed.). San Diego: Harcourt Brace & Company.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Kendall Walton, lan Proops, Peter Ludlow, Jason Stanley, Jessica Wilson, Gabriel Segal and Anthony Everett for very helpful comments on previous drafts. Thanks especially to John Perry, whose assistance from the beginning of this project has been invaluable. Thanks also to audiences at the Institut Jean Nicod (March 2005), the University of Michigan Aesthetics Discussion Group (November 2002) and the NEH Institute in Art, Mind, and Cognitive Science at College Park, Maryland (July 2002) where I presented early versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stacie Friend.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Friend, S. The great beetle debate: a study in imagining with names. Philos Stud 153, 183–211 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9485-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9485-4

Keywords

Navigation