Skip to main content
Log in

Well-ordered science and public trust in science

  • S.I.: Responsible Research and Innovation
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Building, restoring and maintaining well-placed trust between scientists and the public is a difficult yet crucial social task requiring the successful cooperation of various social actors and institutions. Kitcher’s (Science in a democratic society, Prometheus Books, Amherst, 2011) takes up this challenge in the context of liberal democratic societies by extending his ideal model of “well-ordered science” that he had originally formulated in his (Science, truth, and democracy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2001). However, Kitcher nowhere offers an explicit account of what it means for the public to invest epistemic trust in science. Yet in order to understand how his extended model and its implementation in the actual world address the problem of trust as well as to evaluate it critically, an explicit account of epistemic public trust in science needs to be given first. In this article we first present such an account and then scrutinize his project of building public trust in science in light of it. We argue that even though Kitcher’s ideal model and his proposals for its implementation in the real world face a number of problems, they can be addressed with the resources of our account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Notable exceptions are Brown (2013) and Wilholt (2014).

  2. This last difference is picked out by survey questions asking members of the public whether they have confidence that scientists “act in the best interests of the public” and trust scientists “to give full and accurate information” about certain topics. For an example see The PEW Research Center’s report (Funk and Kennedy 2016).

  3. This restriction in the scope of our account is in line with Kitcher’s approach. See Kitcher (2011, pp. 155–168).

  4. For further discussion, see Irzık and Kurtulmus (forthcoming).

  5. This qualification is necessary because when inductive risks are not relevant to the public, they need not play a role in the public’s trust. However, this introduces a complication: research that does not appear to be relevant to the public’s welfare may later turn out to be relevant. Thus, there may be cases when we, as individuals, mistakenly assume that considerations of enhanced trust are irrelevant. Such errors on our part are unavoidable. Nevertheless, judgments regarding trust are not made once and for all. We can revise our judgments about trust in the light of new information and correct our errors.

  6. We thank one of the anonymous referees for urging us to clarify this aspect of our account.

  7. To be exact, in contrast to the original formulation, the ideal deliberators now represent the entire world population and future generations, but for our purposes we will focus on a single society.

  8. Kitcher speaks of the system of public knowledge here, but recall that science is its most central and successful component.

  9. This way of numbering is intended to capture the parallel to the conditions in our account.

  10. In a recent article Stephen John has offered a critique of the requirement of transparency. He uses the negative impact of the leaked emails from Climate Research Unit at the University of East Anglia to illustrate his reservations about transparency. As John observes, many of the practices that the scientists whose emails were hacked engaged in were “normal and respectable” (John 2018, p. 81). However, given a set of false background beliefs about how science works, these practices were seen as outrageous and undermined trust. In light of these, John maintains that non-experts’ epistemic interests would be better served in the absence of transparency. Note that he is making a conditional claim: if people have mistaken views about how science operates, then transparency is dangerous. Taken as a whole, Kitcher’s proposal undermines the antecedent of this conditional. When Kitcher’s ideal obtains, people have an accurate understanding of how science works. Nevertheless, John is also making a broader point, which is important. Under non-ideal conditions transparency can have costs. Thus, when we seek to bring about conditions necessary for warranted trust, we should not myopically focus on improving only one set of conditions but pursue a more holistic approach.

  11. We thank one of the anonymous referees for raising the challenge of establishing trust between the tutors and the representative citizens.

  12. For an overview and the evaluation of the deficit model, see Sturgis and Allum (2004).

  13. This assumption is made also by others who argue for the relevance of moral and social values in scientific research and science policy. See, for example, Wilholt (2013).

  14. We discuss this case in more detail in Irzık and Kurtulmus (forthcoming). For informative discussions of this controversy as it played out in the UK, see Boyce (2007) and Fitzpatrick (2004).

  15. When members of the public do not have enhanced epistemic trust in scientists, this does not entail that scientists are at fault. It is possible that in certain cases the public is at fault for withholding enhanced trust. In fact, John argues that parents who demanded higher epistemic standards than the ones employed by scientists in the MMR case were morally wrong to do so. See John (2011).

  16. Diversity can also provide grounds for basic trust. Diversity with respect to gender, class, race and ethnicity can boost the reliability of research by exposing, eliminating or balancing biases and prejudices (Keller 1985; Longino 1990; Nielsen et al. 2017).

  17. For a remarkable attempt to document this quantitatively, see Alsan and Wannamaker (2018). For related philosophical discussions of this case see Grasswick (2010) and Scheman (2001).

  18. For the view that the roles of African Americans in the study have been exaggerated see Washington (2008, pp. 175–177).

References

  • ALLEA. (2018). All European Academies (ALLEA) Newsletter #18, June 2018. http://www.allea.org/wpcontent/uploads/2018/06/ALLEA_Newsletter_Number_15_June_2018-1.pdf

  • Alsan, M., Garrick, O., & Graziani, G. (Unpublished). Does diversity matter for health? Experimental evidence from Oakland. NBER working paper no. 24787. https://www.nber.org/papers/w24787

  • Alsan, M., & Wannamaker, M. (2018). Tuskegee and the health of black men. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 133, 407–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2011). Democracy, public policy, and lay assessments of scientific testimony. Episteme, 8, 144–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. (1986). Trust and Anti-trust. Ethics, 96, 231–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyce, T. (2007). Health, risk and news: The MMR vaccine and the media. New York: Peter Lang Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. B. (2013). Review of Science in a Democratic Society by Philip Kitcher. Minerva, 51, 389–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2013). Review of Science in a Democratic Society by Philip Kitcher. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 64, 901–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drezner, D. W. (2017). The ideas industry: How pessimists, partisans, and plutocrats are transforming the marketplace of ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, S. (2007). Inclusion: The politics of difference in medical research. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, M. (2004). MMR and autism: What parents need to know. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Flory, J., & Kitcher, P. (2004). Global health and the scientific research agenda. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32, 36–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funk, C., & Kennedy, B. (2016). The politics of climate. Washington, DC: Pew Research Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchat, G. (2012). Politicization of science in the public sphere: A study of public trust in the United States, 1974 to 2010. American Sociological Review, 77, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1987). Modelling collective belief. Synthese, 73, 185–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, M. J. (2017). Public misunderstanding of science? Reframing the problem of vaccine hesitancy. Perspectives on Science, 24, 552–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grasswick, H. E. (2010). Scientific and lay communities: Earning epistemic trust through knowledge sharing. Synthese, 177(3), 387–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (2003). Review of Science, Truth and Democracy by Philip Kitcher. Ethics, 113, 423–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton, R. (1994). Deciding to trust, coming to believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 63–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irzık, G., & Kurtulmus, F. (forthcoming). What is epistemic public trust in science? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy007.

  • John, S. (2011). Expert testimony and epistemological free-riding: The MMR controversy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 496–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John, S. (2018). Epistemic trust and the ethics of science communication: Against transparency, openness, sincerity and honesty. Social Epistemology, 32, 75–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, J. H. (2008). The Tuskegee syphilis experiment. In E. J. Emanuel, C. Grady, R. A. Crouch, R. K. Lie, F. G. Miller, & D. Wendler (Eds.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics (pp. 86–96). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keren, A. (2013). Kitcher on well-ordered science: Should science be measured against the outcomes of ideal democratic deliberation? Theoria, 77, 233–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, T. M. (2017). The death of expertise: The Campaign against established knowledge and why it matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, M. W., Alegria, S., Börjeson, L., Etzkowitz, H., Falk-Krzesinski, H. J., Joshi, A., et al. (2017). Gender diversity leads to better science. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114, 1740–1742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J., & Kitcher, P. (2009). Biomedical research, neglected diseases, and well-ordered science. Theoria, 66, 263–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnick, H. E., Keegan, S., & Huddleston, N. (2015). Trust and confidence at the interfaces of the life sciences and society: Does the public trust science? A workshop summary. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 20, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheman, N. (2001). Epistemology resuscitated: objectivity as trustworthiness. In N. Tuana & S. Morgen (Eds.), Engendering rationalities (pp. 23–52). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgis, P., & Allum, N. (2004). Science in society: Re-evaluating the deficit model of public attitudes. Public Understanding of Science, 13, 55–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Washington, H. A. (2008). Medical apartheid: The dark history of medical experimentation on black Americans from colonial times to the present. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2013). Epistemic trust in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 233–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2014). Review of Science in a Democratic Society by Philip Kitcher. Philosophy of Science, 81, 165–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, B. (1996). May the sheep safely graze? A reflexive view of the expert-lay knowledge divide. In S. Lash, B. Szerszynski, & B. Wynne (Eds.), Risk, environment and modernity: Towards a new ecology (pp. 44–83). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the audience members at the workshop, Responsible Research and Innovation (RRI): Coming to Grips with a Contentious Concept, held at the University of Bielefeld on 30 March–1 April 2017 for their feedback on an earlier version of this paper. We are also grateful to Martin Carrier, Torsten Wilholt and the three anonymous referees for this journal for their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gürol Irzik.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Irzik, G., Kurtulmus, F. Well-ordered science and public trust in science. Synthese 198 (Suppl 19), 4731–4748 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02022-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02022-7

Keywords

Navigation