Skip to main content
Log in

(Social) Metacognition and (Self-)Trust

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What entitles you to rely on information received from others? What entitles you to rely on information retrieved from your own memory? Intuitively, you are entitled simply to trust yourself, while you should monitor others for signs of untrustworthiness. This article makes a case for inverting the intuitive view, arguing that metacognitive monitoring of oneself is fundamental to the reliability of memory, while monitoring of others does not play a significant role in ensuring the reliability of testimony.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The cue-based/knowledge-based distinction is not quite the same as Koriat’s distinction between experience-based and theory-based metacognition (Koriat 2006), since there is no requirement that sensitivity to cues manifest itself in the form of a feeling.

  2. Jost et al. (1998) also refer to social metacognition, but they justify this by employing an extremely broad definition of metacognition as involving “any aspect of thinking about thinking”, a definition so broad as to include many entirely disparate phenomena; my conception of social metacognition is much narrower.

  3. As Gelfert has argued (Gelfert 2009), reliance on type 2 monitoring may result in local reductionism collapsing into Reidian credulism, as the sort of innate, subpersonal mechanisms on which type 2 monitoring relies are the very mechanisms invoked by Reid to explain how testimonial knowledge is acquired. This objection is compatible with my argument here.

  4. I rely mainly on Fricker (1994, 1995), but see Fricker (2002, 2004, 2006a, b, c) for recent developments of the view. I have provided a detailed reconstruction of Fricker’s epistemology elsewhere Michaelian (2010); I rely on that reconstruction here without defending it.

  5. While Fricker is an internalist, she acknowledges the importance of reliability, at least as I read her. I set aside the internalist (coherentist) aspect of her argument, as this is irrelevant given MEF. There is also a modal aspect to Fricker’s argument—the blindly trusting subject is supposed to be gullible not only in the sense that her beliefs are formed by an unreliable process but also in the sense that they are unsafe or insensitive. I set this aspect of the argument aside here, as I have dealt with it elsewhere Michaelian (2010).

  6. I rely here on the more detailed critique given in Michaelian (2012a).

  7. Douven and Cuypers (2009) similarly point out that Fricker may overestimate the availability of cues to untrustworthiness.

  8. As noted in Section 4.4.1 below, what affects the reliability of testimonial belief formation is not the overall reliability of evaluations of testimony as honest or dishonest but rather the reliability specifically of evaluations of testimony as honest; but the finding of poor deception detection accuracy establishes that monitoring for deception is not effective, so I set this aside for now.

  9. The accuracy rate needs to be relativized to the base rate of 50 % honest statements; I come back to this below.

  10. Sperber et al. (2010) argue that some of the information required for detection of deception is necessarily acquired in the course of interpretation of communication. But this only goes so far in cutting down the cost of monitoring for dishonesty—meaningful monitoring will clearly require cognitive resources beyond those required for mere comprehension of an utterance. And even where the information is available, resources will still be required to do something with it.

  11. I draw here on Clark and Chalmers’ paper on the extended mind hypothesis (Clark and Chalmers 1998), discussed more fully in Michaelian (2012d), but this sort of picture is implicit in many philosophical discussions of memory (e.g., Burge 1993).

  12. In both the source problem and the process problem, there might be intermediate/indeterminate cases; I set these aside here.

  13. I draw here on Bernecker’s helpful discussion of memory markers in Bernecker (2008), noting where my approach overlaps with his.

  14. Making a different sort of phenomenological proposal, Audi (1995) suggests that remembering is distinguished from imagining by a feeling of having believed; since memory both stores non-endorsed representations and is capable of producing new representations and beliefs, however, this proposal is a non-starter.

References

  • Alicke, Mark D., and Constantine Sedikides. 2009. Self-enhancement and self-protection: What they are and what they do. European Review of Social Psychology 20:1–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, D. Eric, Bella M. DePaulo, and Matthew E. Ansfield. 2002. The development of deception detection skill: A longitudinal study of same-sex friends. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 28(4):536–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Michael L., Tim Oates, Waiyian Chong, and Don Perlis. 2006. The metacognitive loop I: Enhancing reinforcement learning with metacognitive monitoring and control for improved perturbation tolerance. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 18(3):387–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. 1995. Memorial justification. Philosophical Topics 23:31–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, S. 2008. The metaphysics of memory. Springer.

  • Bernecker, S. 2010. Memory: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bond, Charles F., and Bella M. Depaulo. 2006. Accuracy of deception judgments. Personality and Social Psychology Review 10(3):214–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Bond, Charles F., and Bella M. DePaulo. 2008. Individual differences in judging deception: Accuracy and bias. Psychological Bulletin 134(4):477–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. 2008. Evolutionary economics of mental time travel? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(6):219–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brédart, Serge, James Lampinen, and Anne-Catherine Defeldre. 2003. Phenomenal characteristics of cryptomnesia. Memory 11(1):1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C.D. 1925. The mind and its place in nature. New York: The Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Alan S., and Dana R. Murphy. 1989. Cryptomnesia: Delineating inadvertent plagiarism. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 15(3):432–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, Tyler. 1993. Content preservation. The Philosophical Review 102(4):457–488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christ, Shawn E., David C. Van Essen, Jason M. Watson, Lindsay E. Brubaker, and Kathleen B. McDermott. 2009. The contributions of prefrontal cortex and executive control to deception: evidence from activation likelihood estimate meta-analyses. Cerebral Cortex (New York, N.Y.: 1991) 19(7):1557–1566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andy, and David Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58(1):7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C.A.J. 1992. Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, M. 2005. Metacognition in computation: A selected research review. Artificial Intelligence 169(2):104–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craik, Fergus I. 2002. Levels of processing: Past, present ... and future? Memory 10(5/6):305–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, Robert, Pierre Poirier, and Martin Roth. 2004. Epistemological strata and the rules of right reason. Synthese 141(3):287–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., and I. Ravenscroft. 2002. Recreative minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Argembeau, Arnaud, and Martial Van der Linden. 2004. Phenomenal characteristics associated with projecting oneself back into the past and forward into the future: Influence of valence and temporal distance. Consciousness and Cognition 13(4):844–858.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Argembeau, Arnaud, and Martial Van der Linden. 2006. Individual differences in the phenomenology of mental time travel: The effect of vivid visual imagery and emotion regulation strategies. Consciousness and Cognition 15(2):342–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, R. 2008. Epistemic feelings. In Epistemology and emotions, eds. U. Doǧuoǧlu, and D. Kuenzle. Ashgate.

  • de Vito, Stefania, Nadia Gamboz, and Maria A. Brandimonte. 2012. What differentiates episodic future thinking from complex scene imagery? Consciousness and Cognition 21(2):812–813..

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaulo, B.M., D.A. Kashy, S.E. Kirkendol, M.M. Wyer, and J.A. Epstein. 1996. Lying in everyday life. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 70(5):979–995.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaulo, Bella M., James J. Lindsay, Brian E. Malone, Laura Muhlenbruck, Kelly Charlton, and Harris Cooper. 2003. Cues to deception. Psychological Bulletin 129(1):74–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. 2013. Foundations of Metacognition. In Metacognition, mental agency and self-awareness, eds. M. Beran, J. Brandl, J. Perner, and J. Proust. Oxford: Oxford University Press (forthcoming).

  • Dougal, Sonya, and Jonathan W. Schooler. 2007. Discovery misattribution: When solving is confused with remembering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 136(4):577–592.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, Igor, and Stefaan E. Cuypers. 2009. Fricker on testimonial justification. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40(1):36–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dudai, Yadin. 2004. The neurobiology of consolidations, or, how stable is the engram? Annual Review of Psychology 55(1):51–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunlosky, J., and R.A. Bjork, eds. 2008. Handbook of metamemory and memory. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J.St.B.T. 2008. Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 59(1):255–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, James A., Robert S. Feldman, and James M. Tyler. 2004. When accurate beliefs lead to better lie detection1. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 34(4):764–780.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankish, Keith. 2010. Dual-process and dual-system theories of reasoning. Philosophy Compass 5(10):914–926.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. 1994. Against gullibility. In Knowing from words, eds. B.K. Matilal, and A. Chakrabarti, 125–161. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. 2004. Testimony: Knowing through being told. In Handbook of epistemology, eds. I. Niiniluoto, M. Sintonen, and J. Woleński, 109–130. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Fricker, E. 2006a. Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In The epistemology of testimony, eds. J. Lackey, and E. Sosa, 225–253. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Elizabeth. 1995. Telling and trusting: Reductionism and anti-reductionism in the epistemology of testimony. Mind 104(414):393–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Elizabeth. 2002. Trusting others in the sciences: a priori or empirical warrant? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33(2):373–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006b. Second-hand knowledge*. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73(3):592–618.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006c. Varieties of anti-reductionism about testimony-a reply to Goldberg and Henderson. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72(3):618–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, E.J. 1948. Memory. Mind 57(225):16–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, E.J. 1951. A study in memory: A philosophical essay.

  • Gamboz, Nadia, Maria A. Brandimonte, and Stefania De Vito. 2010. The role of past in the simulation of autobiographical future episodes. Experimental Psychology 57(6):419–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garry, Maryanne, Charles Manning, Elizabeth Loftus, and Steven Sherman. 1996. Imagination inflation: Imagining a childhood event inflates confidence that it occurred. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 3(2):208–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, Axel. 2009. Indefensible middle ground for local reductionism about testimony. Ratio 22(2):170–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Daniel T. 1991. How mental systems believe. American Psychologist 46(2):107–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D.T., P.S. Malone, and D.S. Krull. 1990. Unbelieving the unbelievable: Some problems in the rejection of false information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59:601–613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D.T., R.W. Tafarodi, and P.S. Malone. 1993. You can’t not believe everything you read. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65(2):221–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 1979. What is justified belief? In Justification and knowledge: New studies in epistemology, ed. George S. Pappas, 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel (Reprinted in Goldman, Dordrecht. 1992. Liaisons. Cambridge: MIT Press).

  • Goldman, Dordrecht. 1992. Liaisons. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen, A. 1990. Biological signals as handicaps. Journal of Theoretical Biology 144(4):517–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.

  • Hassabis, Demis, and Eleanor A. Maguire. 2009. The construction system of the brain. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364(1521):1263–1271.

  • Hasson, Uri, Joseph P. Simmons, and Alexander Todorov. 2005. Believe it or not: On the possibility of suspending belief. Psychological Science: A Journal of the American Psychological Society/APS 16(7):566–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, Ralph, Stefan M. Herzog, Lael J. Schooler, and Torsten Reimer. 2008. Fluency heuristic: A model of how the mind exploits a by-product of information retrieval. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition 34(5):1191–1206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintzman, Douglas L. 2011. Research strategy in the study of memory: Fads, fallacies, and the search for the “coordinates of truth”. Perspectives on Psychological Science 6(3):253–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1739. A treatise of human nature.

  • Inglehart, R., M. Basanez, and A. Moreno, eds. 1998. Human values and beliefs: A cross-cultural sourcebook. University of Michigan Press.

  • Inglehart, R., M. Basanez, J. Diez-Medrano, L. Halman, and R. Luijkx, eds. 2004. Human beliefs and values: A cross-cultural sourcebook based on the 1999–2002 values surveys. Siglo XXI Editores.

  • James, William. 1890. The Principles of Psychology.

  • Johnson, M.K., and C.L. Raye. 2000. Cognitive and brain mechanisms of false memories and beliefs. In Memory, brain, and belief, eds. D.L. Schacter, and E. Scarry, 35–86. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Marcia K., Carol L. Raye, Karen J. Mitchell, and Elizabeth Ankudowich. 2012. The cognitive neuroscience of true and false memories true and false recovered memories. In Nebraska symposium on motivation, chap 2, vol 58, pp 15–52. New York, NY: Springer New York.

  • Jost, John T., Arie W. Kruglanski, and Thomas O. Nelson. 1998. Social metacognition: An expansionist review. Personality and Social Psychology Review 2(2):137–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. 2006. Metacognition and consciousness. In Cambridge handbook of consciousness, eds. P.D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, and E. Thompson. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, Asher. 1998. Metamemory: The feeling of knowing and its vagaries. In In psychological science, vol. 2: Biological and cognitive aspects, eds. Michel Sabourin, Fergus Craik, and Michèle Robert. Psychology Press.

  • Koriat, A., M. Goldsmith, and A. Pansky. 2000. Toward a psychology of memory accuracy. Annual Review of Psychology 51:481–537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Robert. 1980. Humans as lie detectors. Journal of Communication 30(4):209–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumkale, G.T., and D. Albarracín. 2004. The sleeper effect in persuasion: a meta-analytic review. Psychological Bulletin 130(1):143–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. 2008. Learning from words: Testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepock, C. 2007. Metacognition and intellectual virtue. PhD thesis, University of Alberta, Edmonton.

  • Levin, D. 2002. Change blindness blindness: As visual metacognition. Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(5–6):111–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, T.R. 2010. A few transparent liars: explaining 54 % accuracy in deception detection experiments. In Communication yearbook 34, ed. C.T. Salmon, 41–61. Routledge.

  • Levine, T.R., and R.K. Kim. 2010. Some considerations for a new theory of deceptive communication. In The interplay of truth and deception, eds. M. Knapp, and M. McGlone, 16–34. Routledge.

  • Levine, Timothy R., Hee S. Park, and Steven A. McCornack. 1999. Accuracy in detecting truths and lies: Documenting the veracity effect. Communication Monographs 66(2):125–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Timothy R., Rachel K. Kim, Hee S. Park, and Mikayla Hughes. 2006. Deception detection accuracy is a predictable linear function of message veracity base-rate: A formal test of Park and Levine’s probability model. Communication Monographs 73(3):243–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Timothy R., Rachel K. Kim, and Lauren M. Hamel. 2010. People lie for a reason: Three experiments documenting the principle of veracity. Communication Research Reports 27(4):271–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, D.S. 1994. Memory source monitoring and eyewitness testimony. In Adult eyewitness testimony: Current trends and developments, eds. D.F. Ross, J.D. Read, and M.P. Toglia. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, D. Stephen, and J. Don Read. 2005. The recovered memories controversy: Where do we go from here? In Recovered memories: Seeking the middle ground, 69–93. Wiley.

  • Loftus, Elizabeth F. 2005. Planting misinformation in the human mind: A 30-year investigation of the malleability of memory. Learning & Memory 12(4):361–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loussouarn, A. 2010. De la métaperception à l’agir perceptif. PhD thesis, Institut Jean-Nicod/Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, Paris.

  • Marsh, Richard L., Joshua D. Landau, and Jason L. Hicks. 1997. Contributions of inadequate source monitoring to unconscious plagiarism during idea generation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 23(4):886–897.

  • Martin, C.B., and Max Deutscher. 1966. Remembering. The Philosophical Review 75(2):161–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mascaro, Olivier, and Dan Sperber. 2009. The moral, epistemic, and mindreading components of children’s vigilance towards deception. Cognition 112(3):367–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, Mohan. 2010. Is memory preservation? Philosophical Studies 148(1):3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J.L. 2011. Memory as a constructive process: The parallel-distributed processing approach. In The memory process: Neuroscientific and humanistic perspectives, eds. S. Nalbantian, P. Matthews, and J.L. McClelland, 129–151. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • McCornack, Steven A., and Timothy R. Levine. 1990. When lovers become leery: The relationship between suspicion and accuracy in detecting deception. Communication Monographs 57(3):219–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCornack, S.A., and M.R. Parks. 1986. Deception detection and relational development: The other side of trust. In Communication yearbook 9, ed. M.L. McLaughlin, 377–389. Sage.

  • McKay, Ryan T., and Daniel C. Dennett. 2009. The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32(6):493–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metcalfe, J. 2008. Evolution of metacognition. In Handbook of metamemory and memory, eds. J. Dunlosky, and R.A. Bjork, 29–46. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2008. Testimony as a natural kind. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5(2):180–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2010. In defence of gullibility: The epistemology of testimony and the psychology of deception detection. Synthese 176(3):399–427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2011a. Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology 24(3):323–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2011b. Is memory a natural kind? Memory Studies 4(2):170–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2011c. The epistemology of forgetting. Erkenntnis 74(3):399–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. 2012a. The evolution of testimony: Receiver vigilance, speaker honesty, and the reliability of communication. (forthcoming).

  • Michaelian, K. 2012b. The information effect: Constructive memory, testimony, and epistemic luck. Synthese (forthcoming).

  • Michaelian, K. 2012c. Metacognition and endorsement. Mind & Language 27(3):284–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, Kourken. 2012d. Is external memory memory? Biological memory and extended mind. Consciousness and Cognition (forthcoming).

  • Millar, Murray, and Karen Millar. 1995. Detection of deception in familiar and unfamiliar persons: The effects of information restriction. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior 19(2):69–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, K.J., and M.K. Johnson. 2000. Source monitoring: Attributing mental experiences. In Oxford handbook of memory, eds. E. Tulving, and F.I.M. Craik, 175–95. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Karen J., and Marcia K. Johnson. 2009. Source monitoring 15 years later: What have we learned from fMRI about the neural mechanisms of source memory? Psychological Bulletin 135(4):638–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, T.O., and L. Narens. 1994. Why investigate metacognition? In Metacognition, eds. J. Metcalfe, and A.P. Shimamura, 1–26. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyberg, Lars, Alice S. N. Kim, Reza Habib, Brian Levine, and Endel Tulving. 2010. Consciousness of subjective time in the brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107(51):22356–22359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer, Daniel M. 2008. The secret life of fluency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(6): 237–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Origgi, Gloria. 2004. Is trust an epistemological notion? Episteme 1(01):61–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Origgi, Gloria. 2010. Epistemic vigilance and epistemic responsibility in the liquid world of scientific publications. Social Epistemology 24(3):149–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Origgi, Gloria. 2012. Epistemic injustice and epistemic trust. Social Epistemology 26(2):221–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, Hee S., and Timothy Levine. 2001. A probability model of accuracy in deception detection experiments. Communication Monographs 68(2):201–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. 1993. Warrant and proper function. Oxford.

  • Proust, J. 2006. Rationality and metacognition in non-human animals. In Rational animals, eds. S. Hurley, and M. Nudds, 247–274. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Proust, J. 2008. Epistemic agency and metacognition: An externalist view. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 108:241–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. 1764/1970. An inquiry into the human mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Richter, Tobias, Sascha Schroeder, and Britta Wöhrmann. 2009. You don’t have to believe everything you read: Background knowledge permits fast and efficient validation of information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 96(3):538–558.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, William A., and Miranda C. Feeney. 2009. The comparative study of mental time travel. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13(6):271–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1921. The analysis of mind. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, Daniel L., and Donna R. Addis. 2007. The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362(1481):773–786.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips, Thomas C. 2008. On the correct application of animal signalling theory to human communication. In Proceedings of the 7th international conference on the evolution of language, eds. A.D.M. Smith, K. Smith, and R. Ferrer i Cancho, 275–282. Singapore: World Scientific.

  • Searcy, W.R., and S. Nowicki. 2005. The evolution of animal communication: Reliability and deception in signalling systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Senor, Thomas D. 2007. Preserving preservationism: A reply to lackey. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(1):199–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serota, Kim B., Timothy R. Levine, and Franklin J. Boster. 2010. The prevalence of lying in America: Three studies of self-reported lies. Human Communication Research 36(1):2–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J.D., W.E. Shields, and D.A. Washburn. 2003. The comparative psychology of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition. Behavioural Brain Research 26(3):317–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 2007. A virtue epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spence, Sean A., and Catherine J. Kaylor-Hughes. 2008. Looking for truth and finding lies: The prospects for a nascent neuroimaging of deception. Neurocase 14(1):68–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. 2001. An evolutionary perspective on testimony and argumentation. Philosophical Topics 29:401–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., F. Clément, C. Heintz, O. Mascaro, H. Mercier, G. Origgi, and D. Wilson. 2010. Epistemic vigilance. Mind & Language 25(4):359–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spreng, R. Nathan, Raymond A. Mar, and Alice S. Kim. 2009. The common neural basis of autobiographical memory, prospection, navigation, theory of mind, and the default mode: A quantitative meta-analysis. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 21(3):489–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, Thomas, and Michael C. Corballis. 2007. The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(3):299–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. 1998. Philosophy and memory traces. Cambridge: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Global Deception Research Team. 2006. A world of lies. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 37(1):60–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, Paul. 2006. Testimony, credibility, and explanatory coherence. Erkenntnis 63(3):295–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Valerie. 2010. Towards a metacognitive dual process theory of conditional reasoning. In Cognition and conditions, ed. Mike Oaksford and Nick Chater. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Tulving, E. 1983. Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, Endel. 1993. What is episodic memory? Current Directions in Psychological Science 2(3):67–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J.O. 1967. Memory and imagination. Mind 76(301):83–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verschuere, Bruno, Adriaan Spruyt, Ewout H. Meijer, and Henry Otgaar. 2011. The ease of lying. Consciousness and Cognition 20(3):908–911.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hippel, William, and Robert Trivers. 2011. The evolution and psychology of self-deception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34(1):1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrij, A. 2000. Detecting lies and deceit: The psychology of lying and the implications for professional practice. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrij, A. 2008. Detecting lies and deceit: Pitfalls and opportunities, 2nd edn. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrij, Aldert, Ronald Fisher, Samantha Mann, and Sharon Leal. 2006. Detecting deception by manipulating cognitive load. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10(4):141–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrij, Aldert, Samantha Mann, Ronald Fisher, Sharon Leal, Rebecca Milne, and Ray Bull. 2008. Increasing cognitive load to facilitate lie detection: The benefit of recalling an event in reverse order. Law and Human Behavior 32(3):253–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrij, Aldert, Pär A. Granhag, Samantha Mann, and Sharon Leal. 2011. Outsmarting the liars: Toward a cognitive lie detection approach. Current Directions in Psychological Science 20(1):28–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, A., and A. Zahavi. 1997. The handicap principle: A missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks for comments and discussion to Joëlle Proust, Sam Wilkinson, two anonymous referees, and audiences at the Third Copenhagen Conference in Epistemology (Social Epistemology Research Group, Københavns Universitet), a meeting of the Filosofiska Föreningen at Lunds Universitet (organized by Frank Zenker), and the “Brains, Minds, and Language” workshop at Bogaziçi Üniversitesi (organized by Lucas Thorpe and Ali Salah).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kourken Michaelian.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Michaelian, K. (Social) Metacognition and (Self-)Trust. Rev.Phil.Psych. 3, 481–514 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0099-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0099-y

Keywords

Navigation