Skip to main content
Log in

Perceiving pictures

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I aim to give a new account of picture perception: of the way our visual system functions when we see something in a picture. My argument relies on the functional distinction between the ventral and dorsal visual subsystems. I propose that it is constitutive of picture perception that our ventral subsystem attributes properties to the depicted scene, whereas our dorsal subsystem attributes properties to the picture surface. This duality elucidates Richard Wollheim’s concept of the “twofoldness” of our experience of pictures: the “visual awareness not only of what is represented but also of the surface qualities of the representation.” I argue for the following four claims: (a) the depicted scene is represented by ventral perception, (b) the depicted scene is not represented by dorsal perception, (c) the picture surface is represented by dorsal perception, and (d) the picture surface is not necessarily represented by ventral perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are also many ways of raising this question. Some talk about the experience of seeing something in the picture, some talk about the (not necessarily conscious) perceptual state of seeing something in a picture. It seems that we are capable of perceiving things in pictures unconsciously. We can perceive objects in pictures even if we are not conscious of either the surface or the depicted object, as the widely discussed phenomenon of subliminal priming shows (Strahan et al. 2002; Eimer and Schlaghecken 2003; Greenwald et al. 1996). Perception can be conscious and unconscious and so can perceiving something in a picture. Thus, it seems that perceiving something in a picture does not need to be a conscious experience. I will talk about cases where we consciously see an object in the picture. But as the account of picture perception I give in this paper does not make any reference to consciousness, it can also be applied in the case of unconscious picture perception.

  2. Gombrich’s account of our experience of pictures is inconsistent with the idea of twofoldness. As he said: “is it possible to ‘see’ both the plane surface and the battle horse at the same time? If we have been right so far, the demand is for the impossible. To understand the battle horse is for a moment to disregard the plane surface. We cannot have it both ways…” (Gombrich 1960, p. 279.)

  3. One important consideration in favor of (1) is the following quote: “The seeing appropriate to representations permits simultaneous attention to what is represented and to the representation” (Wollheim 1980, p. 213). But it is not clear whether seeing-in only needs to “permit” simultaneous attention or it is constituted by it.

  4. I have been and I will be using the concepts of “attention” and “conscious attention” interchangeably. This does not mean that I take sides in the grand debate about whether attention is necessary and/or sufficient for consciousness. On this thorny issue, see Campbell (2002) and Prinz (2010).

  5. These results have been questioned as they are difficult to parse with the phenomenon that we also experience the Müller-Lyer illusion in the haptic sense modality (see Heller et al. 2002; Heller et al. 2005; Suzuki and Arashida 1992).

  6. It is important to note that the question I raise here is different from the question about whether egocentric localization is a necessary condition for seeing per se (Walton 1984, 1997; Currie 1995, chapter 2, esp. p. 70; Currie 1991; Carroll 1995, p. 71; see also Warburton 1988; Cohen and Meskin 2008; Nanay 2010b). Even if egocentric localization is not necessary for seeing per se, it is still necessary for dorsal perception.

  7. It is important to distinguish this question from one about how some pictures locate the spectator at a very specific position in relation to the depicted scene. Although this line of thought has often been made in the psychoanalytic tradition of art and film theory (especially in connection with the concept of suture), it has also been discussed in the analytic tradition (for example, in chapter 3 of Wollheim 1987; see also Hopkins 2002). The question I am addressing here is not about the localization of the spectator as dictated by the pictorial space but about the localization of the depicted objects by the spectator.

  8. Noë emphasizes that we can localize even those objects in our egocentric space that we cannot manipulate or physically interact with, as long as we have expectations with regards to how they would change if we moved closer to it—as in the case of the object in the thick plexiglass container (see Noë 2004, chapter 3).

  9. A possible worry about using either of the above notions of localization in egocentric space in order to argue for (b) is the following. Suppose that I’m looking at myself on CCTV and there is an apple in front of me. I can see the apple on the screen and I can also touch it. Further, I do represent the distance between the apple and myself. Doesn’t this mean that I can localize the apple in my egocentric space? If so, then it seems that the argument for (b) does not go through: we dorsally represent the depicted object. This is a complex and interesting case and I cannot address it in sufficient detail here. Note, however, that although I can touch the apple in front of me, I cannot touch the apple that is on the screen. More importantly, although I represent the distance between the apple in front of me and myself, I do not represent the distance between the apple I see on the screen and myself. If I see the apple on the screen, then the object of my perception is the apple on the screen and not the apple in front of me and what matters for egocentric localization is whether I represent the distance between myself and the object of my perception. And in this example, I do not represent the distance between the object of my perception and myself. I may represent the distance between the apple in front of me and myself (as we are in the same space) and I may also represent the distance between the depicted apple and the depicted myself (as they are in the same space), but I do not represent the distance between the depicted apple and myself. Hence, I do not localize it in my egocentric space.

  10. It has been argued that instead of two visual subsystems, we need to talk about three: the ventral, the ventrodorsal and the dorsodorsal. Thus, what has been taken to be one single dorsal subsystem should be divided into two: one responsible for manipulating objects (dorsodorsal) and one responsible for localizing in egocentric space (ventrodorsal) (Rizzolatti and Matelli 2003). My strategy was to show that we do not localize depicted objects in our egocentric space. Thus, the argument I presented in this section, rephrased using the terminology of the three visual subsystems framework, aimed to show that our ventrodorsal visual subsystem does not represent the depicted object.

  11. It is interesting to note that there are occasions where we do not represent the picture surface. Taking aside various anecdotes of insects that tried to fly through the canvas of a still-life, the obvious examples are trompe l’oeil paintings. If we are genuinely fooled by the trompe l’oeil, then we would readily try to reach through the canvas—we would not be aware of the surface. It is a controversial question whether trompe l’oeil paintings count as genuine instances of depiction (Wollheim 1987; Wollheim 1998; Levinson 1998; Feagin 1998; Lopes 2005). Whether or not they do, seeing trompe l’oeil paintings (that is, the experience of being fooled by them, see Lopes 2005 for a detailed analysis of our experience of trompe l’oeil paintings) is not a twofold experience, as we are supposed to be unaware of the fact that it is a picture at all that we are looking at. In other words, being fooled by trompe l’oeil paintings is not seeing-in (but this does not imply that trompe l’oeil paintings are not pictures).

  12. An interesting related phenomenon is anamorphosis: when a surface, or part of a surface, is designed in such a way that one can see something in it only from a specific angle—as in the case of Holbein’s Ambassadors, where the skull can only be seen from a very oblique angle. Note that the problem I am discussing here is importantly different from the problem of anamorphosis. In the case of anamorphosis, the depicted object can only be seen from an oblique angle, whereas the Pirenne problem is about how it is possible that the depicted object that can be seen head on can also be seen from an oblique angle.

  13. This, in itself, says nothing about (d), as ventral representation is not identical to recognition, but only feeds into the latter.

  14. It is important to note that this problem does not arise if the surface of X is the same as that of Y, as they most often are when we look at reproductions of paintings. I will take it for granted in what follows that the two surfaces are different and distinguishable.

  15. These observations can be reproduced by anyone with a poster and a digital camera. In experimental conditions, similar results were shown. See Pirenne (1970) and Sedgwick and Nicholls (1993). Koenderink et al. (2004) seem to suggest the opposite, but it is important to note that the experiments in Koenderink et al. (2004) are supposed to demonstrate that we “always see an object depicted in a frontoparallel pose […] as facing us squarely, whatever the angle of view” (p. 526). In contrast, what I am interested in is not whether we experience the depicted scene as “facing us sqarely,” but whether our experience of the spatial relation between the depicted objects is distorted. And Koenderink et al. (2004) do not talk about how our experience of the spatial relation between the depicted objects changes.

  16. Matthen said that he would be open to such claim though—personal communication.

References

  • Aglioti, S., DeSouza, J. F. X., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5, 679–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ballard, D. H. (1996). On the function of visual representation. In Kathleen Akins (Ed.), Perception (pp. 111–131). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and Content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N. (2001). When does action resist visual illusions? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 385–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N., & Bernardis, P. (2002). Dissociating perception and action in Kanizsa’s compression illusion. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 723–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Busey, T. A., Brady, N. P., & Cutting, J. E. (1990). Compensation is unnecessary for the perception of faces in slanted pictures. Perception & Psychophysics, 48(1), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2011). Sensorimotor knowledge and naïve realism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 666–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (1995). Towards an ontology of the moving image. In C. A. Freeland & T. E. Wartenberg (Eds.), Philosophy and film. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, K. (1960). Looking at pictures. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110, 495–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, T. (1965). Seeing surfaces and physical objects. In M. Black (Ed.), Philosophy in America (pp. 98–114). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Meskin, A. (2008). Photographs as evidence. In Walden Scott (Ed.), Photography and philosophy: essays on the pencil of nature. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1991). Photography, painting and perception. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 49, 23–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1995). Image and Mind: film, philosophy and cognitive science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, J. E. (1987). Rigidity in cinema seen from the front row, side aisle. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 323–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daprati, E., & Gentilucci, M. (1997). Grasping an illusion. Neuropsychologia, 35, 1577–1582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Le Clec’H, G., Koechlin, E., Mueller, M., Dehaene-Lambertz, G., et al. (1998). Imaging unconscious semantic priming. Nature, 395, 597–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eimer, M., & Schlaghecken, F. (2003). Response facilitation and inhibition in subliminal priming. Biological Psychology, 64, 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1985). Molyneux’s question. In G. Evans (Ed.), Collected papers (pp. 364–399). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feagin, S. L. (1998). Presentation and representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56, 234–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., Bülthoff, H. H., & Fahle, M. (2003). Grasp effects of the Ebbinghaus illusion: obstacle avoidance is not the explanation. Experiental Brain Research, 149, 470–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentilucci, M., Cheiffe, S., Daprati, E., Saetti, M. C., & Toni, I. (1996). Visual illusion and action. Neuropsychologia, 34, 369–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillam, B. (1998). Illusions at century’s end. In J. Hochberg (Ed.), Perception and cognition at century’s end (pp. 95–136). San Diego: Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. (1960). Art and illusion. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Humphrey, G. K. (1998). The objects of action and perception. Cognition, 67, 181–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (2004). Sights unseen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art. Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, A. G., Sean, C. D., & Richard, L. A. (1996). Three cognitive markers of unconscious semantic activation. Science, 273, 1699–1702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, M. A., Glick, R., & Morse, B. (1978). Role of two-dimensional surface characteristics in pictorial depth perception. Perception and Motor Skills, 46, 875–881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halloran, T. O. (1989). Picture perception is array specific: viewing angle versus apparent orientation. Perception & Psychophysics, 45, 467–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. A., Brackett, D. D., Wilson, K., Yoneyama, K., Boyer, A., & Steffen, H. (2002). The haptic Müller-Lyer illusion in sighted and blind people. Perception, 31, 1263–1274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. A., McCarthy, M., Schultz, J., Greene, J., Shanley, M., Clark, A., et al. (2005). The influence of exploration mode, orientation, and configuration on the haptic Müller-Lyer illusion. Perception, 34, 1475–1500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image and experience. A philosophical inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2002). Spectator in the picture. In R. Van Gerwen (Ed.), Richard Wollheim and the art of painting (pp. 215–231). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2010). Inflected pictorial experience: its treatment and significance. In C. Abell & K. Bantilaki (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on depiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. in press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2011). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of seeing. The scope and limits of visual cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M., Decety, J., & Michel, F. (1994). Impairment of grasping movements following a bilateral posterior parietal lesion. Neuropsychologia, 32, 369–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenderink, J., van Doorn, A., Kappers, A., & Todd, J. (2004). Pointing out of the picture. Perception, 33, 513–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Króliczak, G., Heard, P., Goodale, M. A., & Gregory, R. L. (2006). Dissociaition of perception and action unmasked by the hollow-face illusion. Brain Research, 1080, 9–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2006). On images: their structure and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (1998). Wollheim on pictorial representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56, 227–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. M. (1996). Understanding pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. M. (2005). Sight and sensibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2006). On being alienated. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 354–410). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing and knowing: a philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2010). Is memory preservation? Philosophical Studies, 148, 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, P. (1994). Seeing double. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 52, 155–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, P. (1996). Perspective’s places. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54, 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, P. (forthcoming). What‟s so funny? Artefacts for imagining.

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2004). Taking twofoldness seriously. Walton on imagination and depiction. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62, 285–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2005). Is twofoldness necessary for representational seeing? British Journal of Aesthetics, 45, 263–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010a). Inflected and uninflected perception of pictures. In C. Abell & K. Bantilaki (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on depiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010b). Transparency and sensorimotor contingencies: do we see through photographs? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 463–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010c). Perception and imagination: amodal perception as mental imagery. Philosophical Studies, 150, 239–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2011a). Do we perceive apples as edible? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92, 305–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2011b). Do we sense modalities with our sense modalities? Ratio 24, 299–310.

  • Nanay, B. (forthcoming a). Action-oriented perception. European Journal of Philosophy.

  • Nanay, B. (forthcoming b). Between Perception and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Newall, M. (2003). A restriction of pictures and some consequences for a theory of depiction. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 61, 381–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2002). On what we see. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 83, 57–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2003). Causation and perception: the puzzle unravelled. Analysis, 63, 93–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, K. (1992). Solving the “real” mysteries of visual perception: the world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46, 461–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1987). Depiction. Philosophical Review, 96, 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pirenne, M. H. (1970). Optics, painting, and photography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Podro, M. (1991). Depiction and the golden calf. In N. Bryson, M. A. Holly, & K. Moxey (Eds.), Visual theory (p. 163). New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Podro, M. (1998). Depiction. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1905/1958). The value of science. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1970). What is a painting? British Journal of Aesthetics, 10, 225–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2010). How do perceptual states become conscious? In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world: new essays on philosophy of perception. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Matelli, M. (2003). Two different streams form the dorsal visual system: anatomy and functions. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 146–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, S. (1995). Perceiving pictorial space. In W. Epstein & S. Rogers (Eds.), Perception of space and motion (pp. 119–163). San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schier, F. (1986). Deeper into pictures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schier, F. (1993). Van Gogh’s boots: the claims of representation. In D. Knowles & J. Skorupski (Eds.), Virtue and Taste. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedgwick, H. A., & Nicholls, A. L. (1993). Cross talk between the picture surface and the pictorial scene: effects on perceived shape. Perception, 22(suppl), 109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strahan, E. J., Spencerand, S. J., & Zanna, M. P. (2002). Subliminal priming and persuasion: striking while the iron is hot. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 556–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki, K., & Arashida, R. (1992). Geometrical haptic illusions revisited: haptic illusions compared with visual illusions. Perception & Psychophysics, 52, 329–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Topper, D. (2000). On anamorphosis: setting some things straight. Leonardo, 33, 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2004). The silence of the senses. Mind, 113, 57–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turnbull, O. H., Driver, J., & McCarthy, R. A. (2004). 2D but not 3D: pictorial depth deficits in a case of visual agnosia. Cortex, 40, 723–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D., Girshick, A. R., & Banks, M. S. (2005). Why pictures look right when viewed from the wrong place. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1401–1410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1984). Transparent pictures. On the nature of photographic realism. Critical Inquiry, 11, 246–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis and make-believe. On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1991). Reply to Reviewers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51, 423–427.

  • Walton, K. (1997). On pictures and photographs. Objections answered. In R. Allen & M. Smith (Eds.), Film theory and philosophy (pp. 60–75). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (2002). Depiction, perception, and imagination. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 60, 27–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warburton, N. (1988). Seeing through ‘seeing through photographs’. Ratio (new series), 1, 64–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westwood, D. A., Danckert, J., Servos, P., & Goodale, M. (2002). Grasping two-dimensional images and three-dimensional objects in visual-form agnosia. Experimental Brain Research, 144, 1432–1106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1980). Seeing-as, seeing-in, and pictorial representation. In Art and its object (2nd ed., pp. 205–226). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1987). Painting as an art. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1998). On pictorial representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56, 217–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Dom Lopes, Mohan Matthen, Joshua Johnson, Nola Semczyszyn, and two anonymous referees. I gave a version of this talk at the 45th Cincinnati Philosophy Colloquium in 2008 and received very useful feedback, especially from Greg Currie, Noel Carroll, John Kulvicki, Mark Rollins and Jesse Prinz.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bence Nanay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nanay, B. Perceiving pictures. Phenom Cogn Sci 10, 461–480 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9219-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9219-x

Keywords

Navigation