Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. La distinción teórico/observacional: ¿favorece o perjudica al realismo científico? (Is the Observational/Theoretical Distinction Negative or Favorable for Scientific Realism?).Christián C. Carman - 2005 - Critica 37 (111):83-96.
    Laudan denuncia una paradoja que recae sobre el realista científico. Por un lado, necesita la distinción teórico/observacional para definir su posición pero, por otro, la disolución de la distinción favorece su argumentación. En este artículo me propongo mostrar que si dentro de la distinción teórico/observacional se identifican dos dicotomías diferentes --una entre entidades observables y no observables y otra entre términos teóricos y no teóricos--, la paradoja se disuelve, pues para la caracterización del realismo hace falta la distinción entre términos (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy of science.Alberto Cordero - 2009 - In Susana Nuccetelli, Ofelia Schutte & Otávio Bueno (eds.), A Companion to Latin American Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 370–382.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Argentina Mexico Brazil Chile and Puerto Rico Peru Other Centers Concluding Remarks References Further Reading.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Collective acceptance and collective social notions.Raimo Tuomela & Wolfgang Balzer - 1998 - Synthese 117 (2):175-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Approximate truth and dynamical theories.Peter Smith - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (2):253-277.
    Arguably, there is no substantial, general answer to the question of what makes for the approximate truth of theories. But in one class of cases, the issue seems simply resolved. A wide class of applied dynamical theories can be treated as two-component theories—one component specifying a certain kind of abstract geometrical structure, the other giving empirical application to this structure by claiming that it replicates, subject to arbitrary scaling for units etc., the geometric structure to be found in some real-world (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Scientific explanation: Conclusiveness conditions on explanation-seeking questions.Matti Sintonen - 2005 - Synthese 143 (1-2):179 - 205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reasoning to hypotheses: Where do questions come?Matti Sintonen - 2004 - Foundations of Science 9 (3):249-266.
    Detectives and scientists are in the business of reasoning from observations to explanations. This they often do by raising cunning questionsduring their inquiries. But to substantiate this claim we need to know how questions arise and how they are nurtured into more specific hypotheses. I shall discuss what the problem is, and then introduce the so-called interrogative model of inquiry which makes use of an explicit logic of questions. On this view, a discovery processes can be represented as a model-based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • When empirical success implies theoretical reference: A structural correspondence theorem.Gerhard Schurz - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (1):101-133.
    Starting from a brief recapitulation of the contemporary debate on scientific realism, this paper argues for the following thesis : Assume a theory T has been empirically successful in a domain of application A, but was superseded later on by a superior theory T * , which was likewise successful in A but has an arbitrarily different theoretical superstructure. Then under natural conditions T contains certain theoretical expressions, which yielded T's empirical success, such that these T-expressions correspond (in A) to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Normische gesetzeshypothesen und die wissenschaftsphilosophische bedeutung Des nichtmonotonen schliessens.Gerhard Schurz - 2001 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 32 (1):65-107.
    Normic Laws and the Significance of Nonmonotonic Reasoning for Philosophy of Science. Normic laws have the form ‘if A then normally B’. They have been discovered in the explanation debate, but were considered as empirically vacuous (§1). I argue that the prototypical (or ideal) normality of normic laws implies statistical normality (§2), whence normic laws have empirical content. In §3–4 I explain why reasoning from normic laws is nonmonotonic, and why the understanding of the individual case is so important here. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Has the periodic table been successfully axiomatized?Eric R. Scerri - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (2):229-243.
    Although the periodic system of elements is central to the study of chemistry and has been influential in the development of quantum theory and quantum mechanics, its study has been largely neglected in philosophy of science. The present article is a detailed criticism of one notable exception, an attempt by Hettema and Kuipers to axiomatize the periodic table and to discuss the reduction of chemistry in this context.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Reviewing Reduction in a Preferential Model‐Theoretic Context.Emma Ruttkamp & Johannes Heidema - 2005 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (2):123 – 146.
    In this article, we redefine classical notions of theory reduction in such a way that model-theoretic preferential semantics becomes part of a realist depiction of this aspect of science. We offer a model-theoretic reconstruction of science in which theory succession or reduction is often better - or at a finer level of analysis - interpreted as the result of model succession or reduction. This analysis leads to 'defeasible reduction', defined as follows: The conjunction of the assumptions of a reducing theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ontology relativized: Reply to Moulines.Stéphanie Ruphy - 2006 - Synthese 151 (3):325 - 330.
    Ontology is taken by Moulines as supervenient on science: what kinds of things there are is determined by our well-confirmed theories. But the fact is that today, science provides us with a multiplicity of well-confirmed theories, each having its own ontological commitments. The modest, ontological form of reduction advocated by Moulines (this volume) restores hope of putting some ontological order in the “huge chaotic supermarket of science”. In this paper I show that any claim on the amount of order obtained (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Structuralist Theory of Science, Focal Issues, New Results, edited by Wolf-gang Balzer and C. Ulises Moulines (Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy, 6).Rudolf Seising - 1999 - Erkenntnis 51 (2-3):353-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Received View, Incommensurability and Comparison of Theories.Gerhard Preyer - 1998 - ProtoSociology 12:40-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical Notices.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (1):227-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Critical scientific realism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book comes to the rescue of scientific realism, showing that reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Philosophical realism holds that the aim of a particular discourse is to make true statements about its subject matter. Ilkka Niiniluoto surveys different kinds of realism in various areas of philosophy and then sets out his own critical realist philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • On the logic of reducibility: Axioms and examples. [REVIEW]Karl-Georg Niebergall - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):27-61.
    This paper is an investigation into what could be a goodexplication of ``theory S is reducible to theory T''''. Ipresent an axiomatic approach to reducibility, which is developedmetamathematically and used to evaluate most of the definitionsof ``reducible'''' found in the relevant literature. Among these,relative interpretability turns out to be most convincing as ageneral reducibility concept, proof-theoreticalreducibility being its only serious competitor left. Thisrelation is analyzed in some detail, both from the point of viewof the reducibility axioms and of modal logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • An “empirical science” of literature.Edmund Nierlich - 2005 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 36 (2):351 - 376.
    In this article the outlines are sketched of an empirical science of literature as close as possible to the model of the natural sciences. This raises the question of what the standards of an empirical science in the strictest sense should generally be. Practical relevance of its results soon turns up as the fundamental condition for an explanatory empirical science, if the ideology of nearing an empirical truth is no longer accepted and a mere pragmatic justification rejected as its insufficient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zur Typologie wissenschaftlicher Entwicklung nach strukturalistischer Deutung.C. Ulises Moulines - 1997 - In Christoph Hubig (ed.), Cognitio Humana - Dynamik des Wissens Und der Werte: Xvii. Deutscher Kongreß Für Philosophie Leipzig 23.–27. September 1996, Kongreßband: Vorträge Und Kolloquien. De Gruyter. pp. 397-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Structuralism vs. Operationalism.C. Ulises Moulines - 1998 - ProtoSociology 12:78-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reply to Ruphy.C. Ulises Moulines - 2006 - Synthese 151 (3):331-334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ontology, reduction, emergence: A general frame.C. Ulises Moulines - 2006 - Synthese 151 (3):313-323.
    In a scientific context, ontological commitments should be considered as supervenient over accepted scientific theories. This implies that the primarily ontological notions of reduction and emergence of entities of different kinds should be reformulated in terms of relations between existing empirical theories. For this, in turn, it is most convenient to employ a model-theoretic view of scientific theories: the identity criterion of a scientific theory is essentially given by a class of models. Accordingly, reduction and emergence are to be seen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Metatheoretical Structuralism: a General Program for Analyzing Science. [REVIEW]C. U. Moulines - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (2-3):255-268.
    In spite of the ‘experimental turn’ now fashionable in the philosophy of science, the question of the structure and identity criteria of scientific theories continues to be a central issue for the philosophical analysis of empirical science. We need a precise metatheory of empirical theories to deal with this issue. Metatheoretical structuralism appears to offer the most adequate approach in this sense so far. First, some basic intuitions about what empirical theories are, and how they are structured, are laid out. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Introduction: Structuralism as a program for modelling theoretical science.C. Ulises Moulines - 2002 - Synthese 130 (1):1-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Eine strukturalistische Modellierung der empirischen Wissenschaft.C. Ulises Moulines - 1999 - Facta Philosophica 1 (1):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Incompatible empirically equivalent theories: A structural explication.Thomas Mormann - 1995 - Synthese 103 (2):203 - 249.
    The thesis of the empirical underdetermination of theories (U-thesis) maintains that there are incompatible theories which are empirically equivalent. Whether this is an interesting thesis depends on how the term incompatible is understood. In this paper a structural explication is proposed. More precisely, the U-thesis is studied in the framework of the model theoretic or emantic approach according to which theories are not to be taken as linguistic entities, but rather as families of mathematical structures. Theories of similarity structures are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Philosophie und struktur.Ulrich Müller - 1994 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 25 (2):261 - 277.
    Philosophy and Structure. On why it is necessary for hermeneutic philosophy to make use of structural theory. In this essay I give reasons for the thesis that hermeneutic philosophy has to adopt considerations on structural theory in order to avoid the paradox of historism. Concepts of structure like 'criticism', 'centralism', 'creativity' etc. possess both a metaphilosophical and an empirical status which enables us to compare and to combine differend and opposed philosophies by means of common structures. Such an hermeneutic reflection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Teoría de conjuntos y ontología.Leticia O. Minhot - 2011 - Arbor 187 (747):25-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Theorienreduktion in den sozialwissenschaften. Eine fallstudie am beispiel der balancetheorien.Klaus Manhart - 1998 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 29 (2):301-326.
    Theory Reduction in the Social Sciences. The example of balance theories. A central topic both in philosophy of science as well as in the empirical sciences is the reconstruction of the relations between theories. In the past comparisons of theories by means of traditional linguistic methods have proved to be extremely difficult and complicated. In this article the reconstruction of intertheoretical relations based on model-theoretical terms is propagated, as formulated within the structuralist view of theories. The efficiency of a model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On a Straw Man in the Philosophy of Science - A Defense of the Received View.Sebastian Lutz - 2012 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 2 (1):77–120.
    I defend the Received View on scientific theories as developed by Carnap, Hempel, and Feigl against a number of criticisms based on misconceptions. First, I dispute the claim that the Received View demands axiomatizations in first order logic, and the further claim that these axiomatizations must include axioms for the mathematics used in the scientific theories. Next, I contend that models are important according to the Received View. Finally, I argue against the claim that the Received View is intended to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • La filosofía de la ciencia y el lenguaje: relaciones cambiantes, alcances y límites.Pablo Lorenzano - 2011 - Arbor 187 (747):69-80.
    This paper consists of three sections. In the first one, some of the main developments in the philosophy of science through the xx century up to the present will be pointed out, and inserted them in the frame of some more general philosophical transformations, such as the so-called “linguistic turn” and “pragmatic turn”, respectively. In the second one, the established connection will be nuanced, from a revision of the work of a “classical” author such as Carnap. Finally, it will be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leyes fundamentales y leyes de la biología.Pablo Lorenzano - 2007 - Scientiae Studia 5 (2):185-214.
    In this paper I discuss the problem of scientific laws in general and laws of biology in particular. After reviewing the debate about the existence of laws in biology, I examine the subject under the light of the structuralist notion of a fundamental law and argue for the law of matching as the fundamental law of genetics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Inconmensurabilidad teórica y comparabilidad empírica: el caso de la genética clásica.Pablo Lorenzano - 2008 - Análisis Filosófico 28 (2):239-279.
    En esta trabajo se analiza la relación existente entre las propuestas de Mendel, de los "redescubridores" -de Vries, Correns y Tschermak-, de Bateson y colaboradores y de Morgan y discípulos, e.e. la historia de la genética "clásica", en términos de "inconmensurabilidad", de forma tal de capturar y precisar tanto la idea de que entre éstas se dan ciertas discontinuidades y rupturas como de que éstas tienen "algo" que ver de algún modo entre sí. En particular, se introducen, con ayuda del (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Fundamental laws and laws of biology.Pablo Lorenzano - 2006 - In Gerhard Ernst & Karl-Georg Niebergall (eds.), Philosophie der Wissenschaft – Wissenschaft der Philosophie. Festschrift für C.Ulises Moulines zum 60. Geburstag. Mentis. pp. 129-155.
    In this paper, I discuss the problem of scientific laws in general and laws of biology in particular. After reviewing the debate around the existence of laws in biology, I examine the subject in the light of the structuralist notion of a fundamental law and argue for the law of matching as the fundamental law of genetics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Estructuras y mecanismos en la fisiología.César Lorenzano - 2010 - Scientiae Studia 8 (1):41-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Estructura y génesis de la teoría humoral de la inmunología.César Lorenzano - 2012 - Agora 31 (2):195-224.
    En este artículo se analiza la teoría humoral de la inmunidad propuesta por Paul Ehrlich en 1900, precedida de un conjunto de brillantes investigaciones que al tiempo que parecieran refutar a la teoría anterior –la teoría celular de la inmunidad– fueron el terreno privilegiado en el que se sustentó. Historiaremos esas teorías y experiencias previas, para presentar a continuación el artículo fundacional de la teoría humoral. Nos basaremos en estos hallazgos para caracterizar la estructura de la teoría, utilizando una versión (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • El lenguaje de la ciencia.César Lorenzano - 2011 - Arbor 187 (747):15-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bas Van Fraassen y la Ley de Hardy-Weinberg: una discusión y desarrolo de su diagnóstico.Pablo Lorenzano - 2008 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 12 (2):121-154.
    The aim of this article is to discuss and develop the diagnose of the Hardy-Weinberg law made by van Fraassen (1987, p. 110), according to which: 1) that law cannot be considered a law used as an axiom for the classical population genetics as a whole, since it is an equilibrium-law that holds only under certain special conditions; 2) it just determines a subclass of models; 3) its generalization shades off into logical vacuity; and 4) more complex variants of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Base empírica global de contrastación, base empírica local de contrastación y aserción empírica de una teoría.Pablo Lorenzano - 2012 - Agora 31 (2):71-107.
    The aim of this article is to contribute to the discussion about the so-called “empirical claim” and “empirical basis” of theory testing. First, the proposals of reconceptualization of the standard notions of partial potential model, intended application and empirical claim of a theory made by Balzer (1982, 1988, 1997a, 1997b, 2006, Balzer, Lauth & Zoubek 1993) and Gähde (1996, 2002, 2008) will be first discussed. Then, the distinction between “global” and “local empirical basis” will be introduced, linking it with that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Lenguaje, ontología y relaciones interteóricas: en favor de un genuino pluralismo ontológico.Olimpia Lombardi & Ana Rosa Pérez Ransanz - 2011 - Arbor 187 (747):43-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Logical Structure of International Trade Theory.Frieder Lempp - 2008 - Erkenntnis 69 (2):227-242.
    In this paper the structuralist approach of theory reconstruction is applied to International Trade Theory. In the basic element the universal laws of the theory are stated and the general concepts are defined in terms of three sets and seven functions. Ricardo’s Theory of Comparative Advantage and the Factor Proportions Theory by Heckscher and Ohlin are reconstructed as specialisations of the basic element. Two intratheoretical constraints are formulated in order to ensure the consistency of the theory. A number of empirical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Defending the Semantic View: what it takes.Soazig Le Bihan - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (3):249-274.
    In this paper, a modest version of the Semantic View is motivated as both tenable and potentially fruitful for philosophy of science. An analysis is proposed in which the Semantic View is characterized by three main claims. For each of these claims, a distinction is made between stronger and more modest interpretations. It is argued that the criticisms recently leveled against the Semantic View hold only under the stronger interpretations of these claims. However, if one only commits to the modest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Transtheoretical structures and deterministic models.Bernhard Lauth - 2002 - Synthese 130 (1):163 - 172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aplicaciones intencionales de la mecánica cuántica.Mariano Lastiri - 2012 - Agora 31 (2):271-285.
    Este trabajo presenta algunas discusiones preliminares a una reconstrucción de la mecánicacuántica desde una perspectiva estructuralista. Intento responder a la pregunta por lostérminos MQ- no teóricos, es decir, qué magnitudes pueden ser medidas con independenciade la ecuación de Schrödinger y de la regla de Born. Uno de los aspectos relevantes que puedeser analizado una vez que se ha respondido a esta pregunta es el problema de la medición.Dado que el problema de la medición está directamente relacionado con el carácter linealde (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The threshold model of scientific change and the continuity of scientific knowledge.Martti Kuokkanen & Timo Tuomivaara - 1994 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 25 (2):327 - 335.
    The continuity thesis of the Poznań school threshold model of the growth of scientific knowledge is considered in the light of the example of Van der Waals' and Boyle-Mariotte's laws. It is argued - using both traditional logical means and the structuralist reconstruction of the example - that the continuity thesis does not hold. A distinction between 'a historical and a systematic point of view' is introduced and it is argued that the continuity thesis of the threshold model presupposes the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The dual foundation of qualitative truth approximation.Theo A. F. Kuipers - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (2):145-179.
    The main formal notion involved in qualitative truth approximation by the HD-method, viz. ‘more truthlike’, is shown to not only have, by its definition, an intuitively appealing ‘model foundation’, but also, at least partially, a conceptually plausible ‘consequence foundation’. Moreover, combining the relevant parts of both leads to a very appealing ‘dual foundation’, the more so since the relevant methodological notions, viz. ‘more successful’ and its ingredients provided by the HD-method, can be given a similar dual foundation. According to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Afterwords.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1993 - In Paul Horwich (ed.), Educational Theory. MIT Press. pp. 311--41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Theoretizität im Logischen Empirismus und im Strukturalismus – erläutert am Fallbeispiel des Neurobiologischen Konstruktivismus.Stephan Kornmesser - 2008 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 39 (1):53-67.
    In this article I will compare two approaches for defining theoretical terms, that of Logical Empirism and that of Structuralism. I will determine explicitly the accounts of theoreticity in both Logical Empirism and Structuralism, and compare them by means of a case study: a structuralistic reconstruction of Neurobiological Constructivism. I will point out that the structuralistic criticism on the account of theoreticity of Logical Empirism is insufficient and that the structuralistic criterion of theoreticity does not satisfy the requirements of demarcation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reflexionen über die struktur der physikalischen sprache.Andreas Kamlah - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (1):39-53.
    The aim of this paper is to discuss how far physics differs frommathematics, and if a philosophy of science which uses mathematics or logicsas a model for physics would be unable to be aware of many importantfeatures of that natural science.Many functions in physics differ from those of mathematics in beingfunctional dependecies and in having a lawlike character.Physical quantities have the character of "`determinables"'', sets ofspecial entities which are presupposed by physical theories.One may suspect that physics also could not be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Claude Lévi-Strauss y el estructuralismo metateórico sneedeano.Juan Manuel Jaramillo - 2012 - Agora 31 (2).
    El objeto de este artículo es mostrar las similitudes que existen entre el estructuralismo metateórico sneedeano y la que considero es la propuesta teórica más desarrollada del estructuralismo francés, la teoría antropológica de Claude Lévi-Strauss, en particular, su teoría de los sistemas elementales de parentesco. Aunque entre el estructuralismo francés de Lévi-Strauss y el estructuralismo metateórico sneedeano sólo existe, como diría Wittgenstein, un “aire de familia”, sin embargo, quiero mostrar que gracias al trabajo algebraico de André Weil y, en particular, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ramsey sentences and the meaning of quantifiers.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Philosophy of Science 65 (2):289-305.
    1. Ramsey Sentences and the Function of Theoretical Concepts. In his famous paper “Theories,” Frank Ramsey introduced a technique of examining a scientific theory by means of certain propositions, dubbed later “Ramsey Sentences.” They are the results of what is often called Ramsey elimination. This prima facie elimination is often presented as a method of dispensing with theoretical concepts in scientific theorizing. The idea is this: Assume that we are given a finitely axiomatized scientific theorywhere O1, O2, … are the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations