Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On the Plurality of Worlds.David Lewis - 1986 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (3):388-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2708 citations  
  • Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   974 citations  
  • On the Plurality of Worlds.David K. Lewis - 1986 - Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
    This book is a defense of modal realism; the thesis that our world is but one of a plurality of worlds, and that the individuals that inhabit our world are only a few out of all the inhabitants of all the worlds. Lewis argues that the philosophical utility of modal realism is a good reason for believing that it is true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2181 citations  
  • The concept of truth in formalized languages.Alfred Tarski - 1956 - In Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Oxford,: Clarendon Press. pp. 152--278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   533 citations  
  • A refutation of an unjustified attack on the axiom of reducibility.John Myhill - 1979 - In Bertrand Russell & George Washington Roberts (eds.), Bertrand Russell memorial volume. New York: Humanities Press. pp. 81--90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays.Frank Plumpton Ramsey - 1925 - London, England: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Edited by R. B. Braithwaite.
    First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   438 citations  
  • Worlds, times, and selves.A. N. Prior - 1977 - London: Duckworth. Edited by Kit Fine.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • VII*—Equivocation and Existence.Timothy Williamson - 1988 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 88 (1):109-128.
    Timothy Williamson; VII*—Equivocation and Existence, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 88, Issue 1, 1 June 1988, Pages 109–128, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Equivocation And Existence.Timothy Williamson - 1988 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 88:109-127.
    Timothy Williamson; VII*—Equivocation and Existence, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 88, Issue 1, 1 June 1988, Pages 109–128, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Everything.Timothy Williamson - 2003 - Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1):415–465.
    On reading the last sentence, did you interpret me as saying falsely that everything — everything in the entire universe — was packed into my carry-on baggage? Probably not. In ordinary language, ‘everything’ and other quantifiers (‘something’, ‘nothing’, ‘every dog’, ...) often carry a tacit restriction to a domain of contextually relevant objects, such as the things that I need to take with me on my journey. Thus a sentence of the form ‘Everything Fs’ is true as uttered in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • Bare possibilia.Timothy Williamson - 1998 - Erkenntnis 48 (2-3):257--73.
    The theorems of the simplest and strongest sensible quantified modal logic include the Barcan Formula and its converse. Both formulas face strong intuitive objections. This paper develops a theory of possibilia to meet those objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Bare possibilia.Timoti Vilijamson - 1998 - Theoria 41 (4):83-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Practical Reflection, by J. David Velleman. [REVIEW]Michael H. Robins - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):949-952.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • A neglected resolution of Russell’s paradox of propositions.Gabriel Uzquiano - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):328-344.
    Bertrand Russell offered an influential paradox of propositions in Appendix B of The Principles of Mathematics, but there is little agreement as to what to conclude from it. We suggest that Russell's paradox is best regarded as a limitative result on propositional granularity. Some propositions are, on pain of contradiction, unable to discriminate between classes with different members: whatever they predicate of one, they predicate of the other. When accepted, this remarkable fact should cast some doubt upon some of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Paradoxes of intensionality.Dustin Tucker & Richmond H. Thomason - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):394-411.
    We identify a class of paradoxes that is neither set-theoretical nor semantical, but that seems to depend on intensionality. In particular, these paradoxes arise out of plausible properties of propositional attitudes and their objects. We try to explain why logicians have neglected these paradoxes, and to show that, like the Russell Paradox and the direct discourse Liar Paradox, these intensional paradoxes are recalcitrant and challenge logical analysis. Indeed, when we take these paradoxes seriously, we may need to rethink the commonly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Reason and the grain of belief.Scott Sturgeon - 2008 - Noûs 42 (1):139–165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Intention-Based Semantics.Stephen Schiffer - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (2):119--156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Précis of Relevance: Communication and Cognition.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):697.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • IX*—Loose Talk.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86 (1):153-172.
    Dan Sperber, Deirdre Wilson; IX*—Loose Talk, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986, Pages 153–172, https://doi.org/10.1093/ar.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Semantic Regularity and the Liar Paradox.Nicholas J. J. Smith - 2006 - The Monist 89 (1):178 - 202.
    My task here is the first one. I do present a consistent formal system and claim that it provides a perfect model of natural languages such as English, but this system involves no surprises. It is none other than the standard framework of classical logic and model theory. The real weight of the argument lies in the claim that the classical framework—without alteration or addition—contains the resources to model what happens when we say in English ‘This sentence is not true’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Prior's Analytic.B. H. Slater - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):76 - 81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Between Logic and Intuition: Essays in Honor of Charles Parsons.W. D. Hart - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1119-1123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wayne A. Davis, Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. [REVIEW]Jennifer M. Saul - 2001 - Noûs 35 (4):631-641.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Speaker meaning, what is said, and what is implicated.Jennifer M. Saul - 2002 - Noûs 36 (2):228–248.
    [First Paragraph] Unlike so many other distinctions in philosophy, H P Grice's distinction between what is said and what is implicated has an immediate appeal: undergraduate students readily grasp that one who says 'someone shot my parents' has merely implicated rather than said that he was not the shooter [2]. It seems to capture things that we all really pay attention to in everyday conversation'this is why there are so many people whose entire sense of humour consists of deliberately ignoring (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types.Bertrand Russell - 1908 - American Journal of Mathematics 30 (3):222-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Toward a Theory of Second-Order Consequence.Augustín Rayo & Gabriel Uzquiano - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):315-325.
    There is little doubt that a second-order axiomatization of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory plus the axiom of choice (ZFC) is desirable. One advantage of such an axiomatization is that it permits us to express the principles underlying the first-order schemata of separation and replacement. Another is its almost-categoricity: M is a model of second-order ZFC if and only if it is isomorphic to a model of the form Vκ, ∈ ∩ (Vκ × Vκ) , for κ a strongly inaccessible ordinal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays.Frank Plumpton Ramsey, R. B. Braithwaite & G. E. Moore - 1931 - Mind 40 (160):476-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Worlds, Times and Selves.Peter van Inwagen - 1980 - Noûs 14 (2):251-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Modality and quantification in S5.A. N. Prior - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (1):60-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The liar paradox.Charles Parsons - 1974 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (4):381 - 412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Paul Grice and the philosophy of language.Stephen Neale - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (5):509 - 559.
    The work of the late Paul Grice (1913–1988) exerts a powerful influence on the way philosophers, linguists, and cognitive scientists think about meaning and communication. With respect to a particular sentence φ and an “utterer” U, Grice stressed the philosophical importance of separating (i) what φ means, (ii) what U said on a given occasion by uttering φ, and (iii) what U meant by uttering φ on that occasion. Second, he provided systematic attempts to say precisely what meaning is by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • On The Plurality of Worlds.Graeme Forbes - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (151):222-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   514 citations  
  • On the Plurality of Worlds.Allen Stairs - 1988 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (2):333-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   543 citations  
  • Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts.Warren Ingber, Kent Bach & Robert M. Harnish - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (1):134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   256 citations  
  • Reason and Language.Richard Heck - 2006 - In Cynthia Macdonald & Graham Macdonald (eds.), McDowell and His Critics. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 22--45.
    John McDowell has often emphasized the fact that the use of langauge is a rational enterprise. In this paper, I explore the sense in which this is so, arguing that our use of language depends upon our consciously knowing what our words mean. I call this a 'cognitive conception of semantic competence'. The paper also contains a close analysis of the phenomenon of implicature and some suggestions about how it should and should not be understood.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • What's So Logical about the “Logical” Axioms?J. H. Harris - 1982 - Studia Logica 41 (2-3):159 - 171.
    Intuitionists and classical logicians use in common a large number of the logical axioms, even though they supposedly mean different things by the logical connectives and quantifiers — conquans for short. But Wittgenstein says The meaning of a word is its use in the language. We prove that in a definite sense the intuitionistic axioms do indeed characterize the logical conquans, both for the intuitionist and the classical logician.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Studies in the Way of Words.D. E. Over - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (160):393-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   431 citations  
  • The liar in context.Michael Glanzberg - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 103 (3):217 - 251.
    About twenty-five years ago, Charles Parsons published a paper that began by asking why we still discuss the Liar Paradox. Today, the question seems all the more apt. In the ensuing years we have seen not only Parsons’ work (1974), but seminal work of Saul Kripke (1975), and a huge number of other important papers. Too many to list. Surely, one of them must have solved it! In a way, most of them have. Most papers on the Liar Paradox offer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. [REVIEW]J. David Velleman - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):277-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • Possible Worlds.P. Forrest - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):171-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Meaning, quantification, necessity: themes in philosophical logic.Martin Davies - 1981 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • Meaning, Quantification, Necessity: Themes in Philosophical Logic.Martin Davies - 1981 - Mind 92 (368):615-618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Meaning, Quantification, Necessity. Themes in Philosophical Logic.John Campbell - 1983 - Philosophical Quarterly 33 (130):107-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Meaning, Expression, and Indication: Reply to Buchanan.Wayne A. Davis - 2013 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):62-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Comparison of Russell's resolution of the semantical antinomies with that of Tarski.Alonzo Church - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (4):747-760.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Meaning, Expression, and Evidence.Ray Buchanan - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):152-157.
    Grice's (1957) analysis of non-natural meaning generated a huge industry, where new analyses were put forward to respond to successively more complex counterexamples. Davis (2003) offers a novel and refreshingly simple analysis of meaning in terms of the expression of belief, where (roughly) an agent expresses the belief that p just in case she performs a publicly observable action with the intention that it be an indication that she occurrently believes that p. I argue that Davis's analysis fails to capture (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A puzzle about meaning and communication.Ray Buchanan - 2010 - Noûs 44 (2):340-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Radical Anti‐Disquotationalism.Andrew Bacon - 2018 - Philosophical Perspectives 32 (1):41-107.
    A number of `no-proposition' approaches to the liar paradox find themselves implicitly committed to a moderate disquotational principle: the principle that if an utterance of the sentence `$P$' says anything at all, it says that $P$ (with suitable restrictions). I show that this principle alone is responsible for the revenge paradoxes that plague this view. I instead propose a view in which there are several closely related language-world relations playing the `semantic expressing' role, none of which is more central to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On a family of paradoxes.Arthur Prior - 1960 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 2 (1):16-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • How to be a Cognitivist about Practical Reason.Jacob Ross - 2009 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4:243-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations