Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Narrative and the Real World: An Argument for Continuity.David Carr - 1986 - History and Theory 25 (2):117-131.
    Narrative and the real world are not mutually exclusive. Life is not a structureless sequence of events; it consists of complex structures of temporal configurations that interlock and receive their meaning from within action itself. It is also not true that life lacks a point of view which transforms events into a story by telling them. Our focus of attention is not the past but the future, because we grasp configurations extending into the future. Action involves the adoption of an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Historiography and Postmodernism: Reconsiderations.Perez Zagorin - 1987 - History and Theory 26 (3):263-274.
    Zagorin presents a critique of F. R. Ankersmit's postmodernist philosophy of history as fallacious and opposed to some of the fundamental convictions and intuitions historians feel about their discipline. It questions Ankersmit's conclusion that the overproduction of historical writings and continuing generation of new interpretations has obliterated the past as an object of knowledge. It argues that Ankersmit's attempt, in accord with Hayden White, to aestheticize historiography and regard it as a linguistic construction indistinguishable from literature, must sever it from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (5 other versions)On what there is1.Willard V. Quine - 2009 - In Michael Cannon Rea (ed.), Arguing about metaphysics. New York: Routledge. pp. 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas.Quentin Skinner - 1969 - History and Theory 8 (1):3-53.
    Emphasis on autonomy of texts presupposes that there are perennial concepts. But researchers' expectations may turn history into mythology of ideas; researchers forget that an agent cannot be described as doing something he could not understand as a description, and that thinking may be inconsistent. They will never uncover voluntary oblique strategies and by treating ideas as units will confuse sentences with statements. On the other hand, a contextual approach to the meaning of texts dismisses ideas as unimportant effects. Neither (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • La logica del potere: storia concettuale come filosofia politica.Giuseppe Duso - 2007 - Monza (Milano): Polimetrica.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (5 other versions)On what there is.W. V. Quine - 1953 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 1-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   275 citations  
  • Presence.Eelco Runia - 2006 - History and Theory 45 (1):1–29.
    For more than thirty years now, thinking about the way we, humans, account for our past has taken place under the aegis of representationalism. In its first two decades, representationalism, inaugurated by Hayden White’s Metahistory of 1973, has been remarkably successful, but by now it has lost much of its vigor and it lacks explanatory power when faced with recent phenomena such as memory, lieux de mémoire, remembrance, and trauma. It might be argued that many of the shortcomings of representationalism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Towards a Philosophy of the History of Thought?Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2009 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 3 (1):25-54.
    There are a large number of disciplines that are interested in the theoretical aspects of the history of thought. Their perspectives and subjects may vary, but fundamentally they have a common research interest: the history of human thinking and its products. Despite this, they are studied in relative isolation. I argue that having different subjects as specific objects of research, such as political or scientific thinking, is not a valid justification for the separation. I propose the formation of a new (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conventions and the understanding of speech acts.Quentin Skinner - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (79):118-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Identity of the History of Ideas.John Dunn - 1968 - Philosophy 43 (164):85 - 104.
    Two types of criticism are frequently levelled at the history of ideas in general and the history of political theory in particular. The first is very much that of historians practising in other fields; that it is written as a saga in which all the great deeds are done by entities which could not, in principle, do anything. In it, Science is always wrestling with Theology, Empiricism with Rationalism, monism with dualism, evolution with the Great Chain of Being, artifice with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • History, the referent, and narrative: Reflections on postmodernism now.Perez Zagorin - 1999 - History and Theory 38 (1):1–24.
    This essay surveys the present position of postmodernism with respect to the effect of its ideas upon historiography. For this purpose it looks at a number of writings by historians that have been a response to postmodernism including the recently published collection of articles, The Postmodern History Reader. The essay argues that, in contrast to scholars in the field of literary studies, the American historical profession has been much more resistant to postmodernist doctrines and that the latters' influence upon the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Historical contextualism: The new historicism?Preston King - 1995 - History of European Ideas 21 (2):209-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reinhart Koselleck: His Concept of the Concept and Neo-Kantianism.Elias Jose Palti - 2011 - Contributions to the History of Concepts 6 (2):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • La "reconstrucción histórica". Acerca de los supuestos epistemológicos de la explicación y narración historiográfica.M. Tozzi - 1996 - Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofia 22 (1):55-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ankersmit and historical representation.John Zammito - 2005 - History and Theory 44 (2):155–181.
    In Historical Representation Frank Ankersmit seeks a juste milieu between postmodern theory and historical practice. But he still insists that the meaning of a historical representation “is not found, but made in and by [the] text.” Thus “there will be nothing, outside the text itself, that can govern or check [the conceptualization].” Accordingly, “a representation itself cannot be interpreted as one large description. I would not hesitate to say that this—and nothing else—is the central problem in the philosophy of history.” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations