Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Margaret Cavendish and the Exiles of the Mind.Anna Battigelli - 2000 - Utopian Studies 11 (1):139-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Qualities.Samuel C. Rickless - 2014 - In Daniel Kaufman (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Seventeenth Century Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 60-86.
    One of the more interesting philosophical debates in the seventeenth century concerned the nature and explanation of qualities. In order to understand these debates, it is important to place them in their proper historical-philosophical context. This book chapter starts with theoretical background in the work of Aristotle and the atomists, and then moves on to survey various theories of motion and rest, light, color, and sound, as well as the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, as represented in the work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Descartes on "What we call color".Lawrence Nolan - 2011 - In Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • History of philosophy in philosophy today; and the case of the sensible qualities.Margaret D. Wilson - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (1):191-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Berkeley on the Mind‐Dependence of Colors.Margaret D. Wilson - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 68 (3-4):249-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Critical Notice.Michael Tye - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):245-247.
    In 1995, in my book, Ten Problems of Consciousness, I proposed a version of the theory of phenomenal consciousness now known as representationalism. The present book, in part, consists of a further development of that theory along with replies to common objections. It is also concerned with two prominent challenges for any reductive theory of consciousness: the explanatory gap and the knowledge argument. In addition, it connects representationalism with two more general issues: the nature of color and the location of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   397 citations  
  • Of primary and secondary qualities.A. D. Smith - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (2):221-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Colloquium 9.Christopher Shields - 1995 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11 (1):307-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The particularity and phenomenology of perceptual experience.Susanna Schellenberg - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 149 (1):19-48.
    I argue that any account of perceptual experience should satisfy the following two desiderata. First, it should account for the particularity of perceptual experience, that is, it should account for the mind-independent object of an experience making a difference to individuating the experience. Second, it should explain the possibility that perceptual relations to distinct environments could yield subjectively indistinguishable experiences. Relational views of perceptual experience can easily satisfy the first but not the second desideratum. Representational views can easily satisfy the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Descartes’s Dualism.Marleen Rozemond - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In her first book, Marleen Rozemond explicates Descartes's aim to provide a metaphysics that would accommodate mechanistic science and supplant scholasticism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Descartes on mind-body interaction: What's the problem?Marleen Rozemond - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):435-467.
    I argue that Descartes treated the action of body on mind differently from the action of mind on body, as was common in the period. Descartes explicitly denied that there is a problem for interaction but his descriptions of interaction seem to suggest that he thought there was a problem. I argue that these descriptions are motivated by a different issue, the seemingly arbitrary connections between particular physical states and the particular mental states they produce. Within scholasticism there was already (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Margaret Cavendish on Motion and Mereology.Alison Peterman - 2019 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (3):471-499.
    Recent exciting work on Cavendish’s natural philosophy highlights the important role of motion in her system. But what is motion, according to Cavendish? I argue that motion, for Cavendish, is what I call ‘compositional motion’: for a body to be in motion is just for it to divide from some matter and join with other matter. So when Cavendish claims to reduce all natural change to motion, she is really reducing all natural change to mereological change. Cavendish also uses ‘motion’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Empress vs. Spider-Man: Margaret Cavendish on pure and applied mathematics.Alison Peterman - 2019 - Synthese 196 (9):3527-3549.
    The empress of Margaret Cavendish’s The Blazing World dismisses pure mathematicians as a waste of her time, and declares of the applied mathematicians that “there [is] neither Truth nor Justice in their Profession”. In Cavendish’s theoretical work, she defends the Empress’ judgments. In this paper, I discuss Cavendish’s arguments against pure and applied mathematics. In Sect. 3, I develop an interpretation of some relevant parts of Cavendish’s metaphysics and epistemology, focusing on her anti-abstractionism and what I call her ’assimilation’ view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Margaret Cavendish's Epistemology.Kourken Michaelian - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (1):31 – 53.
    This paper provides a systematic reconstruction of Cavendish's general epistemology and a characterization of the fundamental role of that theory in her natural philosophy. After reviewing the outlines of her natural philosophy, I describe her treatment of 'exterior knowledge', i.e. of perception in general and of sense perception in particular. I then describe her treatment of 'interior knowledge', i.e. of self-knowledge and 'conception'. I conclude by drawing out some implications of this reconstruction for our developing understanding of Cavendish's natural philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Reliable Misrepresentation and Tracking Theories of Mental Representation.Angela Mendelovici - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (2):421-443.
    It is a live possibility that certain of our experiences reliably misrepresent the world around us. I argue that tracking theories of mental representation have difficulty allowing for this possibility, and that this is a major consideration against them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Descartes on Life and Sense.Ann Wilbur MacKenzie - 1989 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (2):163 - 192.
    My aim … is to show that the celestial machine is likened not to a kind of divine living being but rather to a clockwork. I consider the human body to be a machine … Although it may exaggerate to say that Descartes fathered the mechanization of biology, it is true that his Treatise of Man provided the first systematic development of the idea that a complete understanding of all the phenomena of life, including all abilities and behaviour of animals, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Descartes on Sensory Representation: A Study of the Dioptrics.Ann Wilbur MacKenzie - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (sup1):109-147.
    The notion of representation figures centrally both in Descartes’ scientific theorizing about sense in humans and in his conceptual speculations about the nature of human cognition.Descartes’ philosophical innovation in the Dioptrics is the claim that sensing in humans is a kind of representing rather than a kind of resembling. This provides the cornerstone for his attack on traditional theories of sense, and it underwrites his own position that sensing is a kind of thinking, ascribable to the rational soul rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Descartes on Sensory Representation: A Study of the Dioptrics.Ann Wilbur MacKenzie - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 16:109-147.
    The notion of representation figures centrally both in Descartes’ scientific theorizing about sense in humans and in his conceptual speculations about the nature of human cognition.Descartes’ philosophical innovation in the Dioptrics is the claim that sensing in humans is a kind of representing rather than a kind of resembling. This provides the cornerstone for his attack on traditional theories of sense, and it underwrites his own position that sensing is a kind of thinking, ascribable to the rational soul rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Legacy of Margaret Cavendish.Eric Lewis - 2001 - Perspectives on Science 9 (3):341-365.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The role of the concept of sense in Principles IV, 189–98.Laura Keating - 2004 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (2):199 – 222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mechanism and the Representational Nature of Sensation in Descartes.Laura Keating - 1999 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):411-429.
    Commentators have argued that along with adopting a mechanical view of nature, Descartes developed two innovative views concerning sensation: sensation occurs without the involvement of an entity resembling the sensation, and sensations represent features of objects but without resembling them. When Descartes is interpreted as making both of these claims, it appears that in removing resemblance from the causal process of sensation, Descartes preserves the notion that sensations represent features of objects and that he does this by introducing a new (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How to speak of the colors.Mark Johnston - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (3):221-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   539 citations  
  • The philosophical innovations of Margaret Cavendish.Susan James - 1999 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (2):219 – 244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Primary Quality View of Color.Frank Jackson - 1996 - Philosophical Perspectives 10:199-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Color Primitivism.David R. Hilbert & Alex Byrne - 2006 - Erkenntnis 66 (1-2):73 - 105.
    The typical kind of color realism is reductive: the color properties are identified with properties specified in other terms (as ways of altering light, for instance). If no reductive analysis is available — if the colors are primitive sui generis properties — this is often taken to be a convincing argument for eliminativism. That is, realist primitivism is usually thought to be untenable. The realist preference for reductive theories of color over the last few decades is particularly striking in light (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • A Problem For Relational Theories of Color.Edward Wilson Averill & Allan Hazlett - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):140-145.
    We argue that relationalism entails an unacceptable claim about the content of visual experience: that ordinary ‘red’ objects look like they look like they look like they’re red, etc.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Can There be Colors in the Dark? Physical Color Theory Before Newton.Henry Guerlac - 1986 - Journal of the History of Ideas 47 (1):3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Problem For Relational Theories of Color.Allan Hazlett Edward Wilson Averill - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):140-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Descartes and the Meditations.Georges Dicker - 2005 - Philosophical Review 114 (1):122-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reason and Freedom: Margaret Cavendish on the order and disorder of nature.Karen Detlefsen - 2007 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89 (2):157-191.
    According to Margaret Cavendish the entire natural world is essentially rational such that everything thinks in some way or another. In this paper, I examine why Cavendish would believe that the natural world is ubiquitously rational, arguing against the usual account, which holds that she does so in order to account for the orderly production of very complex phenomena (e.g. living beings) given the limits of the mechanical philosophy. Rather, I argue, she attributes ubiquitous rationality to the natural world in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • XIII*—Descartes on Colour.John Cottingham - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 (1):231-246.
    John Cottingham; XIII*—Descartes on Colour, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 1990, Pages 231–246, https://doi.org/10.1093/ari.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Descartes on Colour.John Cottingham - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90:231 - 246.
    John Cottingham; XIII*—Descartes on Colour, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 1990, Pages 231–246, https://doi.org/10.1093/ari.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Color properties and color ascriptions: A relationalist manifesto.Jonathan Cohen - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (4):451-506.
    Are colors relational or non-relational properties of their bearers? Is red a property that is instantiated by all and only the objects with a certain intrinsic (/non-relational) nature? Or does an object with a particular intrinsic (/non-relational) nature count as red only in virtue of standing in certain relations - for example, only when it looks a certain way to a certain perceiver, or only in certain circumstances of observation? In this paper I shall argue for the view that color (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Descartes's causal likeness principle.Kenneth C. Clatterbaugh - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (3):379-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Observations upon Experimental Philosophy.Margaret Cavendish & Eileen O'neill - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214):175-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Color realism and color science.Alex Byrne & David R. Hilbert - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):3-21.
    The target article is an attempt to make some progress on the problem of color realism. Are objects colored? And what is the nature of the color properties? We defend the view that physical objects (for instance, tomatoes, radishes, and rubies) are colored, and that colors are physical properties, specifically types of reflectance. This is probably a minority opinion, at least among color scientists. Textbooks frequently claim that physical objects are not colored, and that the colors are "subjective" or "in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • Descartes on sensible qualities.Jill Vance Buroker - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (4):585-611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Descartes on Sense Qualities.Jill Vance Buroker - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (4):585.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Margaret Cavendish on Perception, Self‐Knowledge, and Probable Opinion.Deborah Boyle - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (7):438-450.
    Scholarly interest in Margaret Cavendish's philosophical views has steadily increased over the past decade, but her epistemology has received little attention, and no consensus has emerged; Cavendish has been characterized as a skeptic, as a rationalist, as presenting an alternative epistemology to both rationalism and empiricism, and even as presenting no clear theory of knowledge at all. This paper concludes that Cavendish was only a modest skeptic, for she believed that humans can achieve knowledge through sensitive and rational perception as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Physicalist theories of color.Paul A. Boghossian & J. David Velleman - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (January):67-106.
    The dispute between realists about color and anti-realists is actually a dispute about the nature of color properties. The disputants do not disagree over what material objects are like. Rather, they disagree over whether any of the uncontroversial facts about material objects--their powers to cause visual experiences, their dispositions to reflect incident light, their atomic makeup, and so on--amount to their having colors. The disagreement is thus about which properties colors are and, in particular, whether colors are any of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Color as a secondary quality.Paul A. Boghossian & J. David Velleman - 1989 - Mind 98 (January):81-103.
    Should a principle of charity be applied to the interpretation of the colour concepts exercised in visual experience? We think not. We shall argue, for one thing, that the grounds for applying a principle of charity are lacking in the case of colour concepts. More importantly, we shall argue that attempts at giving the experience of colour a charitable interpretation either fail to respect obvious features of that experience or fail to interpret it charitably, after all. Charity to visual experience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   267 citations  
  • Hobbes's causal account of sensation.Jeffrey Barnouw - 1980 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (2):115-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The headless woman illusion and the defence of materialism.David Malet Armstrong - 1968 - Analysis 29 (2):48--9.
    The paper tries to rebut an objection to materialism. Anti-Materialists have argued that mental processes do not appear to be mere physical processes in the brain, And that secondary qualities such as sounds do not appear to be mere vibrations in the air. So materialists must admit that introspection and perception involve at least the illusion of the falsity of materialism. Using the headless woman illusion as a model, It is shown how the illusion is generated, And that it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Mechanism, resemblance and secondary qualities: From Descartes to Locke.Keith Allen - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2):273 – 291.
    Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is compared with Descartes’s argument (in the Principles of Philosophy) for the distinction between mechanical modifications and sensible qualities. I argue that following Descartes, Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is an essentially a priori argument, based on our conception of substance, and the constraints on intelligible bodily interaction that this conception of substance sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • XIII*—The Names of Secondary Qualities.Peter Alexander - 1977 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77 (1):203-220.
    Peter Alexander; XIII*—The Names of Secondary Qualities, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 77, Issue 1, 1 June 1977, Pages 203–220, https://doi.or.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Names of Secondary Qualities.Peter Alexander - 1977 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77:203 - iv.
    Peter Alexander; XIII*—The Names of Secondary Qualities, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 77, Issue 1, 1 June 1977, Pages 203–220, https://doi.or.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Visual Perception as Patterning: Cavendish against Hobbes on Sensation.Marcus Adams - 2016 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 33 (3):193-214.
    Many of Margaret Cavendish’s criticisms of Thomas Hobbes in the Philosophical Letters (1664) relate to the disorder and damage that she holds would result if Hobbesian pressure were the cause of visual perception. In this paper, I argue that her “two men” thought experiment in Letter IV is aimed at a different goal: to show the explanatory potency of her account. First, I connect Cavendish’s view of visual perception as “patterning” to the “two men” thought experiment in Letter IV. Second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the Genealogy of Color: A Case Study in Historicized Conceptual Analysis.Zed Adams - 2015 - New York: Routledge.
    In On the Genealogy of Color , Zed Adams challenges widely held philosophical views about the nature of color, exploring the relevance of the history of color science for contemporary debates in color realism/anti-realism and philosophy of mind. Adams argues that the two sides of the contemporary debate on the problem of color realism, Cartesian anti-realism and Oxford realism, are both predicated on an assumption that the concept of color perception is ahistorical and unrevisable. Adams takes issue with this premise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What Colors Could Not Be.Joshua Gert - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (3):128-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Another look at color.Colin McGinn - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (11):537-53.
    In The Subjective View,' I defended (unoriginally) a dispositional theory of color and drew out some consequences of that theory. The dispositional theory (DT) maintains, roughly speaking, that for an object to instantiate a color property is for it to have a disposition to cause experiences as of an object having that property in normal perceivers in normal conditions. This theory has notable merits in capturing (assuming one wants them captured) the subjectivity and relativity of ascriptions of color, while allowing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations