Switch to: Citations

References in:

O Princípio de Verdade (Ensaio de Reconstrução Filosófica da Teoria Aristotélica da Verdade)

Dissertation, Pontificia Universidade Católica de Porto Alegre (Pucrs), Brazil (2005)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristóteles: De Anima Livros I-III (trechos).Lucas Angioni - 1999 - Campinas, Brazil: Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de Campinas.
    Translation of passages of Aristotle's De Anima into Portuguese. The passages are these: I.1, I.4 (the 'Rylean passage'); II.1-6; III.1-8. The translation is preliminary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Significa.[author unknown] - 1936 - Synthese 1 (11):325-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Impossible Worlds: A Modest Approach.Daniel Nolan - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):535-572.
    Reasoning about situations we take to be impossible is useful for a variety of theoretical purposes. Furthermore, using a device of impossible worlds when reasoning about the impossible is useful in the same sorts of ways that the device of possible worlds is useful when reasoning about the possible. This paper discusses some of the uses of impossible worlds and argues that commitment to them can and should be had without great metaphysical or logical cost. The paper then provides an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • An Essay in Formal Ontology.Barry Smith - 1978 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 6 (1):39-62.
    As conceived by analytic philosophers ontology consists in the application of the methods of mathematical logic to the analysis of ontological discourse. As conceived by realist philosophers such as Meinong and the early Husserl, Reinach and Ingarden, it consists in the investigation of the forms of entities of various types. The suggestion is that formal methods be employed by phenomenological ontologists, and that phenomenological insights may contribute to the construction of adequate formal-ontological languages. The paper sketches an account of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Unfair to facts.J. L. Austin - 1961 - In John Langshaw Austin (ed.), Philosophical Papers. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The Cognitive Role of Phantasia in Aristotle.Dorothea Frede - 1995 [1992] - In Martha Craven Nussbaum & Amélie Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De anima. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 279-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Ontologia e Predicação em Aristóteles.Lucas Angioni - 2000 - Campinas, Brazil: Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de Campinas.
    Este livro é um 'ancestral' em pré-print do meu livro de 2006, Introdução à Teoria da Predicação em Aristóteles (ISBN 978-85-268-0716-1), publicado pela Editora da Unicamp (ver https://www.academia.edu/6912408/Introdu%C3%A7%C3%A3o_%C3%A0_teoria_da_predica%C3%A7%C3%A3o_em_Arist %C3%B3teles). O ancestral foi felizmente muito citado, mesmo depois da aparição do livro definitivo em 2006. -/- This is an ancestor (in pré-print) of my 2006 Book, 'Introdução à Teoria da Predicação em Aristóteles' (ISBN 978-85-268-0716-1), published by Editora da Unicamp (see https://www.academia.edu/6912408/Introdu%C3%A7%C3%A3o_%C3%A0_teoria_da_predica%C3%A7%C3%A3o_em_Arist %C3%B3teles). The ancestor was cited by many, even after the definitive book (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The language of thought hypothesis.Murat Aydede - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    A comprehensive introduction to the Language of Though Hypothesis (LOTH) accessible to general audiences. LOTH is an empirical thesis about thought and thinking. For their explication, it postulates a physically realized system of representations that have a combinatorial syntax (and semantics) such that operations on representations are causally sensitive only to the syntactic properties of representations. According to LOTH, thought is, roughly, the tokening of a representation that has a syntactic (constituent) structure with an appropriate semantics. Thinking thus consists in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • A classically-based theory of impossible worlds.Edward N. Zalta - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):640-660.
    The appeal to possible worlds in the semantics of modal logic and the philosophical defense of possible worlds as an essential element of ontology have led philosophers and logicians to introduce other kinds of `worlds' in order to study various philosophical and logical phenomena. The literature contains discussions of `non-normal worlds', `non-classical worlds', `non-standard worlds', and `impossible worlds'. These atypical worlds have been used in the following ways: (1) to interpret unusual modal logics, (2) to distinguish logically equivalent propositions, (3) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • II*—Deliberation and Practical Reason.David Wiggins - 1976 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1):29-52.
    David Wiggins; II*—Deliberation and Practical Reason, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 76, Issue 1, 1 June 1976, Pages 29–52, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Aristotle on sameness and oneness.Nicholas P. White - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (2):177-197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Coherence as a Test for Truth.Robert Stern - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2):296-326.
    This paper sets out to demonstrate that a contrast can be drawn between coherentism as an account of the structure of justification, and coherentism as a method of inquiry. Whereas the former position aims to offer an answer to the ‘regress of justification’ problem, the latter position claims that coherence plays a vital and indispensable role as a criterion of truth, given the fallibility of cognitive methods such as perception and memory. It is argued that ‘early’ coherentists like Bradley and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • VII*—Aristotle On the Rôle of Intellect in Virtue.Richard Sorabji - 1974 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):107-129.
    Richard Sorabji; VII*—Aristotle On the Rôle of Intellect in Virtue, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 74, Issue 1, 1 June 1974, Pages 107–129, htt.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The ontological ground of the alethic modality.Scott A. Shalkowski - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):669-688.
    This paper is concerned with the wholly metaphysical question of whether necessity and possibility rest on nonmodal foundations—whether the truth conditions for modal statements are, in the final analysis, nonmodal. It is argued that Lewis’s modal realism is either arbitrary and stipulative or else it is circular. Even if there were Lewisean possible worlds, they could not provide the grounds for modality. D. M. Armstrong’s combinatorial approach to possibility suffers from similar defects. Since more traditional reductions to cognitive or linguistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Substantial Holism.Theodore Scaltsas - 2015 - Philosophical Inquiry 39 (1):146-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Worlds and modality.Tony Roy - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (3):335-361.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Things and de re modality.Tony Roy - 2000 - Noûs 34 (1):56–84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Łukasiewicz on the Principle of Contradiction.Venanzio Raspa - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Research 24:57-112.
    Łukasiewicz distinguishes three formulations of the principle of contradiction in Aristotle’s works: ontological, logical, and psychological. The first two formulations are equivalent though not synonymous, but neither of them is equivalent to the psychological one, which expresses not a principle but only an empirical law. Furthermore, the principle of contradiction is neither a simple and ultimate law nor is it necessary for conducting an inference, because the syllogism is independent of it. The further explanation of this concept leads Łukasiewicz to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Łukasiewicz on the Principle of Contradiction.Venanzio Raspa - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Research 24:57-112.
    Łukasiewicz distinguishes three formulations of the principle of contradiction in Aristotle’s works: ontological, logical, and psychological. The first two formulations are equivalent though not synonymous, but neither of them is equivalent to the psychological one, which expresses not a principle but only an empirical law. Furthermore, the principle of contradiction is neither a simple and ultimate law nor is it necessary for conducting an inference, because the syllogism is independent of it. The further explanation of this concept leads Łukasiewicz to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Three Grades of Modal Involvement.W. V. Quine - 1953 - Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy 14:65-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Review of W.V. Quine's Three Grades of Modal Involvement. [REVIEW]A. R. Turquette - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (2):168-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Truth and Contradiction.Graham Priest - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (200):305-319.
    I argue that there is nothing about truth as such that prevents contradictions from being true. I argue this by considering the main standard accounts of truth, and showing that they are quite compatible with the existence of true contradictions. Indeed, in many cases, they are actually friendly to the idea.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Frege on truth and reference.Palle Yourgrau - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (1):132-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • An Argument of Aristotle on Non-Contradiction.H. W. Noonan - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):163-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle and the appearances.Paul Nieuwenburg - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (4):551-573.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Aristotle and the AppearancesPaul Nieuwenburg1.G. E. L. owen’s influential article Tithenai ta phainomena1 has had a very special efficacy in converting long-standing suspicions into the certainty of what one might call, without exaggeration, an orthodoxy. One of Owen’s arguments is widely thought to remove, in a quite definite way, all doubt surrounding the interpretation of the ambiguous term ta phainomena, usually rendered ‘the appearances,’ as it figures in one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truthmakers for negative truths.George Molnar - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (1):72 – 86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • La noción de identidad en los "Tópicos".Mario Mignucci - 2002 - Anuario Filosófico 35 (73):313-340.
    Arístotle's notion of identity is investigated on this article. This ínvestigation is focused on Top. I7, where different ways of using of the word `same' are analysed. Two major claims are made. First of all, Aristotle does not seem to be committed to hold that there are different types of identity, The second point concerns contingent identíty. What Aristotle says about numerical identity does not commit him to the view that identity can be contingent and it is consistent with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Essentialism in modal logic.Ruth Barcan Marcus - 1967 - Noûs 1 (1):91-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Aristotle on Kinds of Thinking.Malcolm F. Lowe - 1983 - Phronesis 28 (1):17 - 30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on kinds of thinking.Malcolm F. Lowe - 1983 - In Michael Durrant & Aristotle (eds.), Aristotle's de Anima in Focus. Routledge. pp. 17-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on the homonymy of being.Frank A. Lewis - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):1–36.
    The topic of homonymy, especially the variety of homonymy that has gone under the title, “focal meaning,” is of fundamental importance to large portions of Aristotle’s work-not to mention its central place in the ongoing controversies between Aristotle and Plato. It is quite astonishing, therefore, that the topic should have gone so long without a book-length treatment. And it is all the more gratifying that the new book on homonymy by Christopher Shields should be so comprehensive, and of such uniformly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Homonymy of Being.Frank A. Lewis - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):1-36.
    The topic of homonymy, especially the variety of homonymy that has gone under the title, “focal meaning,” is of fundamental importance to large portions of Aristotle’s work—not to mention its central place in the ongoing controversies between Aristotle and Plato. It is quite astonishing, therefore, that the topic should have gone so long without a book-length treatment. And it is all the more gratifying that the new book on homonymy by Christopher Shields should be so comprehensive, and of such uniformly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pragmatism.William James - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52:623.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Realism and its oppositions.Bob Hale - 1997 - In Bob Hale, Crispin Wright & Alexander Miller (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Wiley. pp. 271--308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • La lógica aristotélica de los predicables.José Miguel Gambra - 1988 - Anuario Filosófico 21 (2):89-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • In defense of aristotelian actualism.G. W. Fitch - 1996 - Philosophical Perspectives 10:53 - 71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Aristotle on matter.Kit Fine - 1992 - Mind 101 (401):35-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Imagination and truth in Aristotle.Joyce Engmann - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):259-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Realism.Michael Dummett - 1982 - Synthese 52 (1):145--165.
    Realism concerning a given subject-matter is characterised as a semantic doctrine with metaphysical consequences, namely as the adoption, for the relevant class of statements, of a truth-conditional theory of meaning resting upon the classical two-valued semantics. it is argued that any departure from classical semantics may, though will not necessarily, be seen as in conflict with some variety of realism. a sharp distinction is drawn between the rejection of realism and the acceptance of a reductionist thesis; though intimately related, neither (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Thoughts.David Bell - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (1):36-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Principle of Non-Contradiction.S. Marc Cohen - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):359-370.
    Critical discussion of Alan Code's paper "Aristotle's Investigation of a Basic Logical Principle: Which Science Investigates the Principle of Non-Contradiction?".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only fonnulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls “phantasia.” The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano’s) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Aristotle and the problem of intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only formulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls "phantasia." The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano's) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Truth.J. L. Austin, P. F. Strawson & D. R. Cousin - 1950 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 24 (1):111-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • Aristotle and the sea battle.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1956 - Mind 65 (257):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Sea Battle.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):388-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • "En torno al" cuadrado ontológico".Ignacio Angelelli - 1985 - Anuario Filosófico 18 (1):23-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Princípio da Não-Contradição e Semântica da Predicação em Aristóteles.Lucas Angioni - 1999 - Analytica. Revista de Filosofia 4 (2):121-158.
    My object is Aristotle's discussion of principle of non-contradiction in the first stretch of Metaphysics IV.4. My main focus rests on the connections between Aristotle's discussion of the principle and some key notions of his (explicit or implied) semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Psychological and Metaphysical Dimensions of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle.Thomas V. Upton - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (3):591 - 606.
    RECENT attempts to explain and justify Aristotle's principle of non-contradiction have focused to a great extent on the dialectical dimension of Aristotle's account. For example, T. Irwin maintains that Aristotle justifies the PNC by arguing that there is a sub-set of dialectical opinions which no one can rationally give up. J. Lear supports the importance of the dialectical dimension by summarizing Aristotle's defense of the PNC as follows: The opponent of the PNC tries to argue dialectically that one should not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Y-a-t-il une intuition des principes chez Aristote?Lambros Couloubaritsis - 1980 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 34 (3):440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations