Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A plea for non-naturalism as constructionism.Luciano Floridi - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (2):269-285.
    Contemporary science seems to be caught in a strange predicament. On the one hand, it holds a firm and reasonable commitment to a healthy naturalistic methodology, according to which explanations of natural phenomena should never overstep the limits of the natural itself. On the other hand, contemporary science is also inextricably and now inevitably dependent on ever more complex technologies, especially Information and Communication Technologies, which it exploits as well as fosters. Yet such technologies are increasingly “artificialising” or “denaturalising” the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Pure Logic of Ground.Kit Fine - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):1-25.
    I lay down a system of structural rules for various notions of ground and establish soundness and completeness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Tarski on truth and logical consequence.John Etchemendy - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):51-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • The modalized Heyting calculus: a conservative modal extension of the Intuitionistic Logic ★.Leo Esakia - 2006 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 16 (3-4):349-366.
    In this paper we define an augmentation mHC of the Heyting propositional calculus HC by a modal operator ?. This modalized Heyting calculus mHC is a weakening of the Proof-Intuitionistic Logic KM of Kuznetsov and Muravitsky. In Section 2 we present a short selection of attractive (algebraic, relational, topological and categorical) features of mHC. In Section 3 we establish some close connections between mHC and certain normal extension K4.Grz of the modal system K4. We define a translation of mHC into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Relatedness and implication.Richard L. Epstein - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (2):137 - 173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Law is Necessarily Vague.Timothy Endicott - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (1):377--83.
    In fact, law is necessarily very vague. So if vagueness is a problem for legal theory, it is a serious problem. The problem has to do with the ideal of the rule of law and with the very idea of law: if vague standards provide no guidance in some cases, how can the life of a community be ruled by law? The problem has long concerned philosophers of law; the papers at this symposium address it afresh by asking what legal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Two Paradoxes of Satisfaction.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2015 - Mind 124 (493):85-119.
    There are two paradoxes of satisfaction, and they are of different kinds. The classic satisfaction paradox is a version of Grelling’s: does ‘does not satisfy itself’ satisfy itself? The Unsatisfied paradox finds a predicate, P, such that Px if and only if x does not satisfy that predicate: paradox results for any x. The two are intuitively different as their predicates have different paradoxical extensions. Analysis reduces each paradoxical argument to differing rule sets, wherein their respective pathologies lie. Having different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The pinocchio paradox.Peter Eldridge-Smith & Veronique Eldridge-Smith - 2010 - Analysis 70 (2):212-215.
    The Pinocchio paradox, devised by Veronique Eldridge-Smith in February 2001, is a counter-example to solutions to the Liar that restrict the use or definition of semantic predicates. Pinocchio’s nose grows if and only if what he is stating is false, and Pinocchio says ‘My nose is growing’. In this statement, ‘is growing’ has its normal meaning and is not a semantic predicate. If Pinocchio’s nose is growing it is because he is saying something false; otherwise, it is not growing. ‘Because’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Pinocchio against the dialetheists.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):306-308.
    Semantic dialetheists astutely dodge Explosion, the logical contagion of everything being true if a single contradiction is true. A dialetheia is contained in their semantics, and sustained by a paraconsistent logic. Graham Priest has shown that this is a solution to the Liar paradox. I use the Pinocchio paradox, devised by Veronique Eldridge-Smith, as a counter-example. The Pinocchio paradox turns on the truth of Pinocchio, whose nose grows if and only if what he is saying is not true, saying ‘My (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pinocchio beards the Barber.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2012 - Analysis 72 (4):749-752.
    The Pinocchio paradox poses one dialetheia too many for semantic dialetheists (Eldridge-Smith 2011). However, Beall (2011) thinks that the Pinocchio scenario is merely an impossible story, like that of the village barber who shaves just those villagers who do not shave themselves. Meanwhile, Beall maintains that Liar paradoxes generate dialetheia. The Barber scenario is self-contradictory, yet the Pinocchio scenario requires a principle of truth for a contradiction. In this and other respects the Pinocchio paradox is a version of the Liar, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inconsistent Languages.Matti Eklund - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):251-275.
    The main thesis of this paper is that we sometimes are disposed to accept false and even jointly inconsistent claims by virtue of our semantic competence, and that this comes to light in the sorites and liar paradoxes. Among the subsidiary theses are that this is an important source of indeterminacy in truth conditions, that we must revise basic assumptions about semantic competence, and that classical logic and bivalence can be upheld in the face of the sorites paradox.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • The octagon of opposition.Edward A. Hacker - 1975 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 (3):352-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The philosophical problem of vagueness.Dorothy Edgington - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (4):371-378.
    Think of the color spectrum, spread out before you. You can identify the different colors with ease. But if you are asked to indicate the point at which one color ends and the next begins, you are at a loss. "There is no such point", is a natural thought: one color just shades gradually into the next.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games.Phan Minh Dung - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 77 (2):321-357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   438 citations  
  • A Truth Value Semantics for Modal Logic.J. Michael Dunn - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):314-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A truth value semantics for modal logic.J. Michael Dunn - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):87--100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Early history of the association for symbolic logic.C. J. Ducasse & Haskell B. Curry - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):255-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Strength of Desires: A Logical Approach.Didier Dubois, Emiliano Lorini & Henri Prade - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (1):199-231.
    The aim of this paper is to propose a formal approach to reasoning about desires, understood as logical propositions which we would be pleased to make true, also acknowledging the fact that desire is a matter of degree. It is first shown that, at the static level, desires should satisfy certain principles that differ from those to which beliefs obey. In this sense, from a static perspective, the logic of desires is different from the logic of beliefs. While the accumulation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generalized possibilistic logic: Foundations and applications to qualitative reasoning about uncertainty.Didier Dubois, Henri Prade & Steven Schockaert - 2017 - Artificial Intelligence 252 (C):139-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The contingent a priori and rigid designators.Keith S. Donnellan - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):12-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Radical interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (1):314-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   367 citations  
  • Radical Interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (3-4):313-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   332 citations  
  • Logical grounds.Fabrice Correia - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic (1):1-29.
    I identify a notion of logical grounding, clarify it, and show how it can be used (i) to characterise various consequence relations, and (ii) to give a precise syntactic account of the notion of “groundedness” at work in the literature on the paradoxes of truth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Commentary and Illocutionary Expressions in Linear Calculi of Natural Deduction.Moritz Cordes & Friedrich Reinmuth - 2017 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 26 (2).
    We argue that the need for commentary in commonly used linear calculi of natural deduction is connected to the “deletion” of illocutionary expressions that express the role of propositions as reasons, assumptions, or inferred propositions. We first analyze the formalization of an informal proof in some common calculi which do not formalize natural language illocutionary expressions, and show that in these calculi the formalizations of the example proof rely on commentary devices that have no counterpart in the original proof. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Principle of Non-Contradiction.S. Marc Cohen - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):359-370.
    Critical discussion of Alan Code's paper "Aristotle's Investigation of a Basic Logical Principle: Which Science Investigates the Principle of Non-Contradiction?".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • A modal theorem-preserving translation of a class of three-valued logics of incomplete information.D. Ciucci & D. Dubois - 2013 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 23 (4):321-352.
    There are several three-valued logical systems that form a scattered landscape, even if all reasonable connectives in three-valued logics can be derived from a few of them. Most papers on this subject neglect the issue of the relevance of such logics in relation with the intended meaning of the third truth-value. Here, we focus on the case where the third truth-value means unknown, as suggested by Kleene. Under such an understanding, we show that any truth-qualified formula in a large range (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Turing A. M.. On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungs problcm. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2 s. vol. 42 , pp. 230–265. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Introduction to Mathematical Logic.S. C. Kleene - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (3):362-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Existence and Description in Formal Logic.Alonzo Church, Dana Scott & Ralph Schoenman - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The semantic paradoxes: A diagnostic investigation.Charles Chihara - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (4):590-618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The Semantic Paradoxes: A Diagnostic Investigation.Charles Chihara & Tyler Burge - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3):995-996.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Graded consequence: further studies.M. K. Chakraborty - 1995 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 5 (2):227-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An epistemic approach to paraconsistency: a logic of evidence and truth.Walter Carnielli & Abilio Rodrigues - 2019 - Synthese 196 (9):3789-3813.
    The purpose of this paper is to present a paraconsistent formal system and a corresponding intended interpretation according to which true contradictions are not tolerated. Contradictions are, instead, epistemically understood as conflicting evidence, where evidence for a proposition A is understood as reasons for believing that A is true. The paper defines a paraconsistent and paracomplete natural deduction system, called the Basic Logic of Evidence, and extends it to the Logic of Evidence and Truth. The latter is a logic of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • On the evaluation of argumentation formalisms.Martin Caminada & Leila Amgoud - 2007 - Artificial Intelligence 171 (5-6):286-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Two semantical approaches to paraconsistent modalities.Juliana Bueno-Soler - 2010 - Logica Universalis 4 (1):137-160.
    In this paper we extend the anodic systems introduced in Bueno-Soler (J Appl Non Class Logics 19(3):291–310, 2009) by adding certain paraconsistent axioms based on the so called logics of formal inconsistency , introduced in Carnielli et al. (Handbook of philosophical logic, Springer, Amsterdam, 2007), and define the classes of systems that we call cathodic . These classes consist of modal paraconsistent systems, an approach which permits us to treat with certain kinds of conflicting situations. Our interest in this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explication as a Method of Conceptual Re-engineering.Georg Brun - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (6):1211-1241.
    Taking Carnap’s classic exposition as a starting point, this paper develops a pragmatic account of the method of explication, defends it against a range of challenges and proposes a detailed recipe for the practice of explicating. It is then argued that confusions are involved in characterizing explications as definitions, and in advocating precising definitions as an alternative to explications. Explication is better characterized as conceptual re-engineering for theoretical purposes, in contrast to conceptual re-engineering for other purposes and improving exactness for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Chunk and permeate, a paraconsistent inference strategy. Part I: The infinitesimal calculus.Bryson Brown & Graham Priest - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (4):379-388.
    In this paper we introduce a paraconsistent reasoning strategy, Chunk and Permeate. In this, information is broken up into chunks, and a limited amount of information is allowed to flow between chunks. We start by giving an abstract characterisation of the strategy. It is then applied to model the reasoning employed in the original infinitesimal calculus. The paper next establishes some results concerning the legitimacy of reasoning of this kind - specifically concerning the preservation of the consistency of each chunk (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The Rules of Logic Composition for the Bayesian Epistemic e-Values.Wagner Borges & Julio Michael Stern - 2007 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 15 (5-6):401-420.
    In this paper, the relationship between the e-value of a complex hypothesis, H, and those of its constituent elementary hypotheses, Hj, j = 1… k, is analyzed, in the independent setup. The e-value of a hypothesis H, ev, is a Bayesian epistemic, credibility or truth value defined under the Full Bayesian Significance Testing mathematical apparatus. The questions addressed concern the important issue of how the truth value of H, and the truth function of the corresponding FBST structure M, relate to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • O terminach modalnych.Ludwik Borkowski - 1958 - Studia Logica 7 (1):7 - 41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Deductive foundation and analytic propositions.Ludwik Borkowski - 1966 - Studia Logica 19 (1):59 - 74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Which Logic for the Radical Anti-Realist ?Denis Bonnay & Mikaël Cozic - unknown
    Since the ground-breaking contributions of M. Dummett (Dummett 1978), it is widely recognized that anti-realist principles have a critical impact on the choice of logic. Dummett argued that classical logic does not satisfy the requirements of such principles but that intuitionistic logic does. Some philosophers have adopted a more radical stance and argued for a more important departure from classical logic on the basis of similar intuitions. In particular, J. Dubucs and M. Marion (?) and (Dubucs 2002) have recently argued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Duality for Involutive Bisemilattices.Stefano Bonzio, Andrea Loi & Luisa Peruzzi - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (2):423-444.
    We establish a duality between the category of involutive bisemilattices and the category of semilattice inverse systems of Stone spaces, using Stone duality from one side and the representation of involutive bisemilattices as Płonka sum of Boolean algebras, from the other. Furthermore, we show that the dual space of an involutive bisemilattice can be viewed as a GR space with involution, a generalization of the spaces introduced by Gierz and Romanowska equipped with an involution as additional operation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logic and Religion.Jean-Yves Beziau & Ricardo Silvestre - 2017 - Logica Universalis 11 (1):1-12.
    This paper introduces the special issue on Logic and Religion of the journal Logica Universalis (Springer). The issue contains the following articles: Logic and Religion, by Jean-Yves Beziau and Ricardo Silvestre; Thinking Negation in Early Hinduism and Classical Indian Philosophy, by Purushottama Bilimoria; Karma Theory, Determinism, Fatalism and Freedom of Will, by Ricardo Sousa Silvestre; From Logic in Islam to Islamic Logic, by Musa Akrami; Leibniz’s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem of Impossible Objects, by Wolfgang (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Trivializing sentences and the promise of semantic completeness.J. Beall - 2015 - Analysis 75 (4):573-584.
    This paper challenges defenders/advocates of the semantic-completeness route towards gluts to explain, in simple and plausible terms, why the ‘trivializer paradox’, framed in terms of closure relatives on theories, fails to undermine their argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Categoricity Spectra for Polymodal Algebras.Nikolay Bazhenov - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (6):1083-1097.
    We investigate effective categoricity for polymodal algebras. We prove that the class of polymodal algebras is complete with respect to degree spectra of nontrivial structures, effective dimensions, expansion by constants, and degree spectra of relations. In particular, this implies that every categoricity spectrum is the categoricity spectrum of a polymodal algebra.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards the Unification of Inconsistency Handling Mechanisms.Diderik Batens - 2000 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 8:5-31.
    It is shown that the consequence relations defined from theRescher-Manor Mechanism are all inconsistency-adaptive logics combined with a specific interpretation schema for the premises. Each of the adaptive logics isobtained by applying a suitable adaptive strategy to the paraconsistent logicCLuN.This result provides all those consequence relations with a proof theory and with a static semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The law of contradiction.Jonathan Barnes - 1969 - Philosophical Quarterly 19 (77):302-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Axioms for abstract model theory.K. J. Barwise - 1974 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 7 (2-3):221-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Expansion of a model of a weakly o-minimal theory by a family of unary predicates.Bektur Sembiuly Baizhanov - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1382-1414.
    A subset A $\subseteq$ M of a totally ordered structure M is said to be convex, if for any a, b $\in A: [a . A complete theory of first order is weakly o-minimal (M. Dickmann [D]) if any model M is totally ordered by some $\emptyset$ -definable formula and any subset of M which is definable with parameters from M is a finite union of convex sets. We prove here that for any model M of a weakly o-minimal theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations