Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Can the mind change the world?Ned Block - 1989 - In George S. Boolos (ed.), Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press. pp. 137--170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong, by Jerry A. Fodor. [REVIEW]R. De Clercq - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 62 (3):609-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   213 citations  
  • Unity of Science.Robert L. Causey - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (4):656-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Reference and Reflexivity.John Perry - 2009 - Critica 41 (123):147-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science.Alexander Rosenberg - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (186):120-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Nothing in Biology Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution.Theodosius Dobzhansky - 1973 - American Biology Teacher 35:125-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • Mental Causation.John Heil & Alfred Mele - 1995 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 185 (1):105-106.
    Common sense and philosophical tradition agree that mind makes a difference. What we do depends not only on how our bodies are put together, but also on what we think. Explaining how mind can make a difference has proved challenging, however. Some have urged that the project faces an insurmountable dilemma: either we concede that mentalistic explanations of behavior have only a pragmatic standing or we abandon our conception of the physical domain as causally autonomous. Although each option has its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • On being ontologically serious.John Heil - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A simple view of colour.John Campbell - 1993 - In John J. Haldane & C. Wright (eds.), Reality: Representation and Projection. Oxford University Press. pp. 257-268.
    Physics tells us what is objectively there. It has no place for the colours of things. So colours are not objectively there. Hence, if there is such a thing at all, colour is mind-dependent. This argument forms the background to disputes over whether common sense makes a mistake about colours. It is assumed that..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Dispositions.Stephen Mumford - 1998 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 32 (1):193-197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • Simulation trouble.Shaun Gallagher - 2007 - Social Neuroscience 2 (3-4):353–365.
    I present arguments against both explicit and implicit versions of the simulation theory for intersubjective understanding. Logical, developmental, and phenomenological evidence counts against the concept of explicit simulation if this is to be understood as the pervasive or default way that we understand others. The concept of implicit (subpersonal) simulation, identified with neural resonance systems (mirror systems or shared representations), fails to be the kind of simulation required by simulation theory, because it fails to explain how neuronal processes meet constraints (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Causation as folk science.John D. Norton - 2003 - In Huw Price & Richard Corry (eds.), Philosophers' Imprint. Oxford University Press.
    I deny that the world is fundamentally causal, deriving the skepticism on non-Humean grounds from our enduring failures to find a contingent, universal principle of causality that holds true of our science. I explain the prevalence and fertility of causal notions in science by arguing that a causal character for many sciences can be recovered, when they are restricted to appropriately hospitable domains. There they conform to a loose collection of causal notions that form a folk science of causation. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • What Mary couldn't know: Belief about phenomenal states.Martine Nida-Rumelin - 1995 - In Thomas Metzinger (ed.), Conscious Experience. Ferdinand Schoningh. pp. 219--41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Species, taxonomy, and systematics.Marc Ereshefsky - 2007 - In Michael Ruse (ed.), Philosophy of Biology. Prometheus Books. pp. 403--428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reduction, Multiple Realizability, and Levels of Reality.Sven Walter & Markus Eronen - 2011 - In Steven French & Juha Saatsi (eds.), Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Continuum. pp. 138.
    The idea of reduction has appeared in different forms throughout the history of science and philosophy. Thales took water to be the fundamental principle of all things; Leucippus and Democritus argued that everything is composed of small, indivisible atoms; Galileo and Newton tried to explain all motion with a few basic laws; 17th century mechanism conceived of everything in terms of the motions and collisions of particles of matter; British Empiricism held that all knowledge is, at root, experiential knowledge; current (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Human Knowledge, Its Scope and Limits.Bertrand Russell - 1949 - Mind 58 (231):369-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • Perception, Common Sense and Science.James W. Cornman - 1978 - Mind 87 (346):310-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reductionism in Biology: Prospects and Problems.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1974 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1974:613 - 632.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Orthogonality of Phenomenality and Content.Gottfried Vosgerau, Tobias Schlicht & Albert Newen - 2008 - American Philosophical Quarterly 45 (4):309 - 328.
    This paper presents arguments from empirical research and from philosophical considerations to the effect that phenomenality and content are two distinct and independent features of mental representations, which are both relational. Thus, it is argued, classical arguments that infer phenomenality from content have to be rejected. Likewise, theories that try to explain the phenomenal character of experiences by appeal to specific types of content cannot succeed. Instead, a dynamic view of consciousness has to be adopted that seeks to explain consciousness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Self-notions.John Perry - 1990
    ”Self-beliefs” are beliefs of the sort one ordinarily has about oneself, and expresses with the first person. These contrast with the beliefs one has in ”Casta˜neda cases,” in which one has a belief about oneself without knowing it. This paper advances an account of the nature of self-belief. According to this account, self-belief is a special case of interacting with things via notions that serve as repositories for information about objects with certain important relations to the knower, and as motivators (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1995 - Journal of the History of Biology 28 (1):172-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   188 citations  
  • Consciousness.William G. Lycan - 1988 - Mind 97 (388):640-642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  • Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre.Moritz Schlick - 1925 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 5 (3):86-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • On Leaving Out What It's Like.Joseph Levine - 1993 - In Martin Davies & Glyn W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological an Philosophical Essays. MIT Press. pp. 543--557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Articulation of Parts Explanation in Biology and the Rational Search for Them.Stuart A. Kauffman - 1970 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1970:257 - 272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Philosophy and our mental life.Hilary Putnam - 1975 - In Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • The nature of pain.Valerie Hardcastle - 2001 - In William P. Bechtel, Pete Mandik, Jennifer Mundale & Robert S. Stufflebeam (eds.), Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader. Blackwell. pp. 295--311.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the persistence of phenomenology.Diana Raffman - 1995 - In Thomas Metzinger (ed.), Conscious Experience. Ferdinand Schoningh. pp. 293–308.
    In Thomas Metzinger, Conscious Experience, Schoningh Verlag. 1995. [ online ].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on the sciences of cognition and the brain.William P. Bechtel - manuscript
    1. The Naturalistic Turn in Philosophy of Science 2. The Framework of Mechanistic Explanation: Parts, Operations, and Organization 3. Representing and Reasoning About Mechanisms 4. Mental Mechanisms: Mechanisms that Process Information 5. Discovering Mental Mechanisms 6 . Summary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The inner sense of action: Agency and motor representations.Vittorio Gallese - 2000 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (10):23-40.
    Discusses the possibility of reconciling different articulations of intentionality from a neurobiological perspective. The author analyzes the relationship between agency and representation and how representation is intrinsically related to action control. The author also presents a new account of action, arguing against what is still commonly held as its proper definition, namely the final outcome of a cascade-like process that starts from the analysis of sensory data, incorporates the result of decision processes, and ends up with responses (actions) to externally-or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Outing the Mind.Robert Van Gulick - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter. pp. 255--284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem.William C. Wimsatt - 1976 - In Gordon G. Globus (ed.), Consciousness and the Brain. Plenum Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Species and Taxonomy.Richard Richards - 2008 - In Michael Ruse (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology. Oxford University Press. pp. 161-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations