Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Donald Kalish and Richard Montague. Logic. Techniques of formal reasoning. Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., New York and Burlingame 1964, x + 350 pp. [REVIEW]B. H. Mayoh - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):641-642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Grundlagen der Mathematik I. Hilbert & Bernays - 1935 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 42 (2):12-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1981 - In David Zaret (ed.), Review of Thomas S. Kuhn The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Duke University Press. pp. 320--39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   418 citations  
  • On sense and nominatum.Gottlob Frege - 1949 - In Herbert Feigl (ed.), Readings in philosophical analysis. New York,: Appleton-Century-Crofts. pp. 85-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • On referring.P. F. Strawson - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning.Donald Kalish, Richard Montague & Gary Mar - 1964 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press USA. Edited by Richard Montague.
    Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning, 2/e is an introductory volume that teaches students to recognize and construct correct deductions. It takes students through all logical steps--from premise to conclusion--and presents appropriate symbols and terms, while giving examples to clarify principles. Logic, 2/e uses models to establish the invalidity of arguments, and includes exercise sets throughout, ranging from easy to challenging. Solutions are provided to selected exercises, and historical remarks discuss major contributions to the theories covered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • On referring.Peter F. Strawson - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):320-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   614 citations  
  • Things.Richard Sharvy - 1969 - The Monist 53 (3):488-504.
    This group of sentences is used by Quine in a well-known attack on quantified modal logic and the possibility of meaningful modalized predication. Modalized predication would involve specifying some object, and asserting of it that necessarily or possibly it has some given property φ. If this can be done sensibly, then the modal context ‘necessarily φx’ can be quantified into, and conversely. So modalized predication and quantifying into modal contexts are bound up together. Quine thinks that neither is very sensible, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Descriptions as variables.Paolo Santorio - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (1):41-59.
    On a popular view dating back to Russell, descriptions, both definite and indefinite alike, work syntactically and semantically like quantifiers. I have an argument against Russell's view. The argument supports a different picture: descriptions can behave syntactically and semantically like variables. This basic idea can be implemented in very different systematic analyses, but, whichever way one goes, there will be a significant departure from Russell. The claim that descriptions are variables is not new: what I offer is a new way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 1905 - Mind 14 (56):479-493.
    By a `denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1205 citations  
  • How to say goodbye to the third man.Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Edward N. Zalta - 2000 - Noûs 34 (2):165–202.
    In (1991), Meinwald initiated a major change of direction in the study of Plato’s Parmenides and the Third Man Argument. On her conception of the Parmenides , Plato’s language systematically distinguishes two types or kinds of predication, namely, predications of the kind ‘x is F pros ta alla’ and ‘x is F pros heauto’. Intuitively speaking, the former is the common, everyday variety of predication, which holds when x is any object (perceptible object or Form) and F is a property (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • On the logic of the ontological argument.Paul E. Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 1991 - Philosophical Perspectives 5:509-529.
    In this paper, the authors show that there is a reading of St. Anselm's ontological argument in Proslogium II that is logically valid (the premises entail the conclusion). This reading takes Anselm's use of the definite description "that than which nothing greater can be conceived" seriously. Consider a first-order language and logic in which definite descriptions are genuine terms, and in which the quantified sentence "there is an x such that..." does not imply "x exists". Then, using an ordinary logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • The Philosophical Significance of Gödel’s Slingshot.Stephen Neale - 1995 - Mind 104 (416):761-825.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Descriptions.D. E. Over - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172):392-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Do Modal Distinctions Collapse in Carnap’s System?Genoveva Marti - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (6):575 - 593.
    Føllesdal (1966 and 1969) claims that modal distinctions collapse, that is that p and Necessarily p are equivalent, in any system of modal logic that incorporates a standard theory of definite descriptions, like the one proposed by Carnap in M&N. I argue that his argument fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning.E. G. K. Lopez-Escobar - 1967 - Philosophical Review 76 (2):252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Karel Lambert, Free Logic: Selected Essays. [REVIEW]M. Randall Holmes - 2003 - Studia Logica 75 (3):413-419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Russell’s Notion of Scope.Saul A. Kripke - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1005-1037.
    Despite the renown of ‘On Denoting’, much criticism has ignored or misconstrued Russell's treatment of scope, particularly in intensional, but also in extensional contexts. This has been rectified by more recent commentators, yet it remains largely unnoticed that the examples Russell gives of scope distinctions are questionable or inconsistent with his own philosophy. Nevertheless, Russell is right: scope does matter in intensional contexts. In Principia Mathematica, Russell proves a metatheorem to the effect that the scope of a single occurrence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Marti on Descriptions in Carnap’s S.Michael Kremer - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (6):629-634.
    This note is a friendly amendment to Marti's analysis of the failure of Føllesdal's argument that modal distinctions collapse in Carnap's logic S2. Føllesdal's argument turns on the treatment of descriptions. Marti considers how modal descriptions, which Carnap banned, might be handled; she adopts an approach which blocks Føllesdal's argument, but requires a separate treatment of non-modal descriptions. I point out that a more general treatment of descriptions in S2 is possible, and indeed is implicit in Marti's informal discussion, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • An argument concerning the unknowable.Leon Horsten - 2009 - Analysis 69 (2):240-242.
    Williamson has forcefully argued that Fitch's argument shows that the domain of the unknowable is non-empty. And he exhorts us to make more inroads into the land of the unknowable. Concluding his discussion of Fitch's argument, he writes: " Once we acknowledge that [the domain of the unknowable] is non-empty, we can explore more effectively its extent. … We are only beginning to understand the deeper limits of our knowledge. " I shall formulate and evaluate a new argument concerning the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Grundlagen der Mathematik.S. C. Kleene - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):16-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Descriptions and unknowability.Jan Heylen - 2010 - Analysis 70 (1):50-52.
    In a recent paper Horsten embarked on a journey along the limits of the domain of the unknowable. Rather than knowability simpliciter, he considered a priori knowability, and by the latter he meant absolute provability, i.e. provability that is not relativized to a formal system. He presented an argument for the conclusion that it is not absolutely provable that there is a natural number of which it is true but absolutely unprovable that it has a certain property. The argument depends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Carnap’s Theory of Descriptions and its Problems.Jan Heylen - 2010 - Studia Logica 94 (3):355-380.
    Carnap's theory of descriptions was restricted in two ways. First, the descriptive conditions had to be non-modal. Second, only primitive predicates or the identity predicate could be used to predicate something of the descriptum . The motivating reasons for these two restrictions that can be found in the literature will be critically discussed. Both restrictions can be relaxed, but Carnap's theory can still be blamed for not dealing adequately with improper descriptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the termination of russell’s description elimination algorithm.Clemens Grabmayer, Joop Leo, Vincent van Oostrom & Albert Visser - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):367-393.
    In this paper we study the termination behavior of Russell’s description elimination rewrite system. We discuss certain claims made by Kripke (2005) in his paper concerning the possible nontermination of elimination of descriptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Descriptions as predicates.Delia Graff Fara - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (1):1-42.
    Although Strawson’s main aim in “On Referring” was to argue that definite descriptions can be used referentially – that is, “to mention or refer to some individual person or single object . . . , in the course of doing what we should normally describe as making a statement about that person [or] object” (1950, p. 320) – he denied that definite descriptions are always used referentially. The description in ‘Napoleon was the greatest French soldier’ is not used referentially, says (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.R. M. Martin - 1957 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 18 (4):558-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (1):92-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning. [REVIEW]J. R. Cameron - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (66):81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Generalized quantifiers and natural language.John Barwise & Robin Cooper - 1981 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2):159--219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   595 citations  
  • Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Language.Jon Barwise - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4:159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • Principia mathematica, to *56.Alfred North Whitehead & Bertrand Russell - 1962 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Bertrand Russell & Alfred North Whitehead.
    The great three-volume Principia Mathematica is deservedly the most famous work ever written on the foundations of mathematics. Its aim is to deduce all the fundamental propositions of logic and mathematics from a small number of logical premisses and primitive ideas, and so to prove that mathematics is a development of logic. This abridged text of Volume I contains the material that is most relevant to an introductory study of logic and the philosophy of mathematics (more advanced students will wish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases.Irene Heim - 1982 - Dissertation, Umass Amherst
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   593 citations  
  • More free logic.Scott Lehmann - 2002 - In Dov Gabbay & Franz Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 5. New York: Springer. pp. 197-259.
    By a free logic is generally meant a variant of classical first-order logic in which constant terms may, under interpretation, fail to refer to individuals in the domain D over which the bound variables range, either because they do not refer at all or because they refer to individuals outside D. If D is identified with what is assumed by the given interpretation to exist, in accord with Quine’s dictum that “to be is to be the value of a [bound] (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Free logic.John Nolt - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Descriptions.Peter Ludlow - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Uber Sinn und Bedeutung.Gottlob Frege - 1892 - Zeitschrift für Philosophie Und Philosophische Kritik 100 (1):25-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   738 citations  
  • What is Frege's theory of descriptions?Bernard Linsky & Jeffry Pelletier - 2005 - In On Denoting: 1905-2005. München: Philosophia. pp. 195-250.
    In the case of an actual proper name such as ‘Aristotle’ opinions as to the Sinn may differ. It might, for instance, be taken to be the following: the pupil of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great. Anybody who does this will attach another Sinn to the sentence ‘Aristotle was born in Stagira’ than will a man who takes as the Sinn of the name: the teacher of Alexander the Great who was born in Stagira. So long as the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Free Logic: Selected Essays.Karel Lambert - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (4):521-523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • An Introduction to Formal Logic.Peter Smith - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):563-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Descriptions.S. Neale - 1996 - Critica 28 (83):97-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   310 citations