Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth.Stathis Psillos - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    Scientific realism is the optimistic view that modern science is on the right track: that the world really is the way our best scientific theories describe it. In his book, Stathis Psillos gives us a detailed and comprehensive study which restores the intuitive plausibility of scientific realism. We see that throughout the twentieth century, scientific realism has been challenged by philosophical positions from all angles: from reductive empiricism, to instrumentalism and to modern sceptical empiricism. _Scientific Realism_ explains that the history (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   579 citations  
  • 2. Heidegger's Hermeneutic Realism.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1991 - In David R. Hiley, James Bohman & Richard Shusterman (eds.), The Interpretive turn: philosophy, science, culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. pp. 25-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude.Martin Heidegger - 1995 - Indiana University Press.
    This work, the text of Martin Heidegger's lecture course of 1929/30, is crucial for an understanding of Heidegger's transition from the major work of his early years, Being and Time, to his later preoccupations with language, truth, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • Truth and other enigmas.Michael Dummett - 1978 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    A collection of all but two of the author's philosophical essays and lectures originally published or presented before August 1976.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   436 citations  
  • Heidegger on Realism and the Correspondence Theory of Truth.John Tietz - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (1):59-.
    In An Introduction to Metaphysics Heidegger asserted that “it wasnot German idealism that collapsed; rather, the age was no longer strong enough to sustain the greatness, breadth, and originality of that spiritual world, i.e., truly to realize it”. He was at this point launchinginto one of the major themes of his later work: the “darkening of the world” in the form of the materialism and “demonism” typified by the antitheses of the USSR and the USA, a polarity of seeming opposites (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Heidegger on Realism and Idealism.Mark Basil Tanzer - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Research 23:95-111.
    This paper concerns the relation of Heidegger’s thought to the traditionally opposed positions of realism and idealism: a dilemma that Heidegger explicitly addresses in Section 43 of Being and Time. Heidegger’s attempt to forge a position ‘between’ realism and idealism has recently been interpreted in a number of ways, depending on whether Heidegger’s affinity with realism or his affinity with idealism is prioritized. My contention is that Heidegger’s realist and idealist dimensions are equally essential to his thought in view of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger on Realism and Idealism.Mark Basil Tanzer - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Research 23:95-111.
    This paper concerns the relation of Heidegger’s thought to the traditionally opposed positions of realism and idealism: a dilemma that Heidegger explicitly addresses in Section 43 of Being and Time. Heidegger’s attempt to forge a position ‘between’ realism and idealism has recently been interpreted in a number of ways, depending on whether Heidegger’s affinity with realism or his affinity with idealism is prioritized. My contention is that Heidegger’s realist and idealist dimensions are equally essential to his thought in view of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger’s Critique of Realism.Mark Tanzer - 1995 - Southwest Philosophy Review 11 (2):145-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger: Between Idealism and Realism.Lambert V. Stepanich - 1991 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1):20-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Heidegger: Between Idealism and Realism.Lambert V. Stepanich - 1991 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1):20-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Vampires: Social constructivism, realism, and other philosophical undead.Joseph Rouse - 2002 - History and Theory 41 (1):60–78.
    Social Constructivism and the Philosophy of Science by Andre Kukla The Social Construction of What? by Ian Hacking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Review: Vampires: Social Constructivism, Realism, and Other Philosophical Undead. [REVIEW]Joseph Rouse - 2002 - History and Theory 41 (1):60-78.
    Social Constructivism and the Philosophy of Science by Andre Kukla The Social Construction of What? by Ian Hacking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Knowledge and power: toward a political philosophy of science.Joseph Rouse - 1987 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    This lucidly written book examines the social and political significance of the natural sciences through a detailed and original account of science as an interpretive social practice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Kuhn, Heidegger, and scientific realism.Joseph Rouse - 1981 - Man and World 14 (3):269-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Engaging science: how to understand its practices philosophically.Joseph Rouse - 1996 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Summarizing this century's major debates over realism and the rationality of scientific knowledge, Joseph Rouse believes that these disputes oversimplify the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Heidegger and Peirce.Sandra B. Rosenthal - 1988 - Southwest Philosophy Review 4 (1):103-110.
    In both the phenomenological ontology of Martin Heidegger and the pragmatism of Charles Peirce, the rejection of the Kantian phenomenal/noumenal distinction leads to a rejection of the alternatives of realism or idealism as well. In their respective denials of such an existential or ontological gap between appearance or phenomena and the ontologically real, they each establish a fundamental intentional unity between man and world which cannot be understood within the framework of realism or of idealism and which reveals deeply rooted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical Notice.Stathis Psillos - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2):495-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Realism, Reliabilism, and the 'Strong Programme' in the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.Jeff Kochan - 2008 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (1):21 – 38.
    In this essay, I respond to Tim Lewens's proposal that realists and Strong Programme theorists can find common ground in reliabilism. I agree with Lewens, but point to difficulties in his argument. Chief among these is his assumption that reliabilism is incompatible with the Strong Programme's principle of symmetry. I argue that the two are, in fact, compatible, and that Lewens misses this fact because he wrongly supposes that reliabilism entails naturalism. The Strong Programme can fully accommodate a reliabilism which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Coping with Things-in-themselves: A Practice-Based Phenomenological Argument for Realism.Hubert L. Dreyfus & Charles Spinosa - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (1):49-78.
    Against Davidsonian (or deflationary) realism, it is argued that it is coherent to believe that science can in principle give us access to the functional components of the universe as they are in themselves in distinction from how they appear to us on the basis of our quotidian concerns or sensory capacities. The first section presents the deflationary realist's argument against independence. The second section then shows that, although Heidegger pioneered the deflationary realist account of the everyday, he sought to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Heidegger and the problem of idealism.Piotr Hoffman - 2000 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 43 (4):403 – 411.
    Was Heidegger a 'realist' or an 'idealist'? The issue has been and continues to be hotly debated in Heidegger scholarship. Here it is argued that the much more desirable realistic interpretation of Heidegger can be sustained, provided his theory of moods is given its due. Moods, I argue, are not only 'equiprimordial' with Dasein's understanding of being, but are also irreducible to the latter. It is often held - correctly, as it seems to the author - that Heidegger's idealism is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Role of the Beiträge in Heidegger’s Critique of Science.Trish Glazebrook - 2001 - Philosophy Today 45 (1):24-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger on the Experiment.Trish Glazebrook - 1998 - Philosophy Today 42 (3):250-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Heidegger's philosophy of science.Trish Glazebrook - 2000 - New York: Fordham University Press.
    This book concerns itself with an issue that is not sufficiently addressed in the literature: Heidegger’s philosophy of science. Although a great deal of attention is paid to Heidegger’s later critique of technology, no one has systematically studied how he understood “science.” Many readers will be surprised to learn, through this book, that Heidegger developed the essentials of a fairly sophisticated philosophy of science, one that in many ways invites comparison with that of Thomas Kuhn. Glazebrook demonstrates that Heidegger’s philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • From ϕvσις to Nature, τε′χνη to Technology: Heidegger on Aristotle, Galileo, and Newton.Trish Glazebrook - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):95-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From ϕvσις to Nature, τε′χνη to Technology: Heidegger on Aristotle, Galileo, and Newton.Trish Glazebrook - 2000 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):95-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Heidegger and scientific realism.Trish Glazebrook - 2001 - Continental Philosophy Review 34 (4):361-401.
    This paper describes Heidegger as a robust scientific realist, explains why his view has received such conflicting treatment, and concludes that the special significance of his position lies in his insistence upon linking the discussion of science to the question of its relation with technology. It shows that Heidegger, rather than accepting the usual forced option between realism and antirealism, advocates a realism in which he embeds the antirealist thesis that the idea of reality independent of human understanding is unintelligible. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Familiar and the Strange: On the Limits of Praxis in the Early Heidegger.Joseph P. Fell - 1990 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (S1):23-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Realism and truth.Michael Devitt - 1984 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    This second edition includes a new Afterword by the author.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   286 citations  
  • On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1974 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 286-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   407 citations  
  • On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47:5-20.
    Davidson attacks the intelligibility of conceptual relativism, i.e. of truth relative to a conceptual scheme. He defines the notion of a conceptual scheme as something ordering, organizing, and rendering intelligible empirical content, and calls the position that employs both notions scheme-content dualism. He argues that such dualism is untenable since: not only can we not parcel out empirical content sentence per sentence but also the notion of uninterpreted content to which several schemes are relative, and the related notion of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   577 citations  
  • World, World‐entry, and realism in early Heidegger.David R. Cerbone - 1995 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 38 (4):401 – 421.
    Interpretations of Heidegger's Being and Time have tended to founder on the question of whether he is in the end a realist or an idealist, in part because of Heidegger's own rather enigmatic remarks on the subject. Many have thus depicted him as being in some way ambivalent, and so as holding on to an unstable combination of the two opposing positions. Recently, William Blattner has explained the apparent ambivalence by appealing to Kant's transcendental/empirical distinction. Although an ingenious reading of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Heidegger’s Categories in Being and Time.Robert Brandom - 1983 - The Monist 66 (3):387-409.
    In Division One of Being and Time Heidegger presents a novel categorization of what there is, and an original account of the project of ontology and consequently of the nature and genesis of those ontological categories. He officially recognizes two categories of Being: Zuhandensein and Vorhandensein. Vorhandene things are roughly the objective, person-independent, causally interacting subjects of natural scientific inquiry. Zuhandene things are those which a neo-Kantian would describe as having been imbued with human values and significances. In addition to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Heidegger and Peirce.Patrick L. Bourgeois & Sandra B. Rosenthal - 1988 - Southwest Philosophy Review 4 (1):103-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is Heidegger a Kantian idealist?William D. Blattner - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):185 – 201.
    It is argued that Heidegger should be seen as something of a Kantian Idealist. Like Kant, Heidegger distinguishes two standpoints (transcendental and empirical) which we can occupy when we ask the question whether natural things depend on us. He agrees with Kant that from the empirical or human standpoint we are justified in saying that natural things do not depend on us. But in contrast with Kant, Heidegger argues that from the transcendental standpoint we can say neither that natural things (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Heidegger's Kantian idealism revisited.William Blattner - 2004 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (4):321 – 337.
    I offer a revised interpretation of Heidegger's ontological idealism, his thesis that being, but not entities, depends on Dasein ? as well as its relationship to Kant's transcendental idealism. I build from my earlier efforts on this topic by modifying them and defending my basic line of interpretation against criticisms advanced by Cerbone, Philipse, and Carman. In essence, my reading of Heidegger goes like this: what it means to say that "being" depends on Dasein is that the criteria and standards (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Representing and Intervening.Ian Hacking - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (4):381-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   730 citations  
  • Representational Mind: A Study of Kant's Theory of Knowledge.Martin Heidegger - 1983 - Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
    Continues and extends explorations begun in Being and Time.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • The Glance of the Eye: Heidegger, Aristotle, and the Ends of Theory.William McNeill - 1999 - State University of New York Press.
    Argues that Heidegger's early reading of Aristotle provides him with a critical resource for addressing the problematic domination of theoretical knowledge in Western civilization.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • How Scientific Practices Matter: Reclaiming Philosophical Naturalism.Joseph Rouse - 2002 - University of Chicago Press.
    How can we understand the world as a whole instead of separate natural and human realms? Joseph T. Rouse proposes an approach to this classic problem based on radical new conceptions of both philosophical naturalism and scientific practice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Heidegger and science.Joseph J. Kockelmans - 1985 - Washington, D.C.: University Press of America.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The social construction of what?Ian Hacking - 1999 - Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
    Especially troublesome in this dispute is the status of the natural sciences, and this is where Hacking finds some of his most telling cases, from the conflict ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   617 citations  
  • Truth and Other Enigmas.Michael Dummett - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (122):47-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   294 citations  
  • Heidegger on the Problem of Reality.Ka-Wing Leung - 2006 - New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 6 (1):169-184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • .Richard Alston - 2015
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Arguing for the Natural Ontological Attitude.Joseph Rouse - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:294 - 301.
    Arthur Fine has recently argued that standard realist and anti-realist interpretations of science should be replaced by "natural ontological attitude" (NOA). I ask whether Fine's own justification for NOA can meet the standards of argument that underlie his criticisms of realism and anti-realism. Fine vacillates between two different ways of advocating NOA. The more minimalist defense ("why not try NOA?") begs the question against both realists and antirealists. A stronger program, based on Fine's arguments for a "no-theory" of truth, has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Basic Problems of Phenomenology.M. Heidegger - 1982 - In Trans Albert Hofstadter (ed.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • 10 How Heidegger defends the possibility of a correspondence theory of truth with respect to the entities of natural science.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 2002 - In Hubert L. Dreyfus & Mark A. Wrathall (eds.), Heidegger Reexamined. Routledge. pp. 4--219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Realism and Truth.Michael Devitt - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):657-663.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Representing and Intervening.Ian Hacking - 1987 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 92 (2):279-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   569 citations  
  • Engaging Science: How to Understand Its Practices Philosophically.Joseph Rouse - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (2):359-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations