Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Sense and sensitivity: how focus determines meaning.David I. Beaver - 2008 - Malden, MA: Blackwell. Edited by Brady Z. Clark.
    Sense and Sensitivity explores the semantics and pragmatics of focus in natural language discourse, advancing a new account of focus sensitivity which posits a three-way distinction between different effects of focus. Makes a valuable contribution to the ongoing research in the field of focus sensitivity Discusses the features of QFC, an original theory of focus implying a new typology of focus-sensitive expressions Presents novel cross-linguistic data on focus and focus sensitivity Concludes with a case study of exclusives (like “only”), arguing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Strategies for scope taking (1997).Anna Szabolcsi - 1997 - In Ways of Scope Taking. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Standard theories of scope are semantically blind. They employ a single logico-syntactic rule of scope assignment quantifying in Quantifier Raising, storage, or type change etc which roughly speaking prefixes an expression \aplha.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The dynamics of sophisticated laziness.J. van der Does - 1993 - In ¸ Itegroenendijk1993. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation (Illc), University of Amsterdam. pp. 1-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Total and partial predicates and the weak and strong interpretations.Youngeun Yoon - 1996 - Natural Language Semantics 4 (3):217-236.
    This paper introduces an interesting class of predicates that come in pairs, so-called total and partial predicates. It will be shown that such predicates contribute to an explanation for the weak and strong interpretations of donkey sentences. This paper proposes that the phenomenon of weak and strong interpretations is real, and that whether a sentence receives the weak or the strong interpretation depends on the predicate in the nuclear scope of the sentence. It also proposes that sum individuals are calculated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Plurals, presuppositions and the sources of distributivity.Roger Schwarzschild - 1993 - Natural Language Semantics 2 (3):201-248.
    This paper begins with a discussion ofcumulativity (e.g., ‘P(a) & P(b) implies P(a+b)’), formalized using a verb phrase operator. Next, the meanings of distributivity markers such aseach and non-distributivity indicators such astogether are considered. An existing analysis ofeach in terms of quantification over parts of a plurality is adopted. However,together is problematic, for it involves a cancellation or negation of the quantification associated witheach. (The four boys together owned exactly three cars could not be true if each of the boys (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Combining Montague semantics and discourse representation.Reinhard Muskens - 1996 - Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (2):143 - 186.
    This paper embeds the core part of Discourse Representation Theory in the classical theory of types plus a few simple axioms that allow the theory to express key facts about variables and assignments on the object level of the logic. It is shown how the embedding can be used to combine core analyses of natural language phenomena in Discourse Representation Theory with analyses that can be obtained in Montague Semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Scorekeeping in a language game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):339--359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   908 citations  
  • Polarity in Natural Language: Predication, Quantification and Negation in Particular and Characterizing Sentences.Sebastian Löbner - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (3):213-308.
    The present paper is an attempt at the investigation of the nature of polarity contrast in natural languages. Truth conditions for natural language sentences are incomplete unless they include a proper definition of the conditions under which they are false. It is argued that the tertium non datur principle of classical bivalent logical systems is empirically invalid for natural languages: falsity cannot be equated with non-truth. Lacking a direct intuition about the conditions under which a sentence is false, we need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Pragmatic halos.Peter Lasersohn - 1999 - Language 75 (3):522-551.
    It is a truism that people speak ‘loosely’——that is, that they often say things that we can recognize not to be true, but which come close enough to the truth for practical purposes. Certain expressions. such as those including ‘exactly’, ‘all’ and ‘perfectly’, appear to serve as signals of the intended degree of approximation to the truth. This article presents a novel formalism for representing the notion of approximation to the truth, and analyzes the meanings of these expressions in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • E-Type Pronouns, I-Sums, and Donkey Anaphora.Shalom Lappin & Nissim Francez - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (4):391-428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Two methods to find truth-value gaps and their application to the projection problem of homogeneity.Manuel Križ & Emmanuel Chemla - 2015 - Natural Language Semantics 23 (3):205-248.
    Presupposition, vagueness, and oddness can lead to some sentences failing to have a clear truth value. The homogeneity property of plural predication with definite descriptions may also create truth-value gaps: The books are written in Dutch is true if all relevant books are in Dutch, false if none of them are, and neither true nor false if, say, half of the books are written in Dutch. We study the projection property of homogeneity by deploying methods of general interest to identify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Weak vs. strong Readings of donkey sentences and monotonicity inference in a dynamic setting.Makoto Kanazawa - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (2):109 - 158.
    In this paper, I show that the availability of what some authors have called the weak reading and the strong reading of donkey sentences with relative clauses is systematically related to monotonicity properties of the determiner. The correlation is different from what has been observed in the literature in that it concerns not only right monotonicity, but also left monotonicity (persistence/antipersistence). I claim that the reading selected by a donkey sentence with a double monotone determiner is in fact the one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Singular donkey pronouns are semantically singular.Makoto Kanazawa - 2001 - Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (3):383-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • From Discourse to Logic: Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic and Discourse Representation Theory.Hans Kamp & Uwe Reyle - 1993 - Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Preface This book is about semantics and logic. More specifically, it is about the semantics and logic of natural language; and, even more specifically than ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   455 citations  
  • Uniqueness.Nirit Kadmon - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (3):273 - 324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora.Irene Heim - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (2):137--77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   189 citations  
  • The Question–Answer Requirement for scope assignment.Andrea Gualmini, Sarah Hulsey, Valentine Hacquard & Danny Fox - 2008 - Natural Language Semantics 16 (3):205-237.
    This paper focuses on children’s interpretation of sentences containing negation and a quantifier (e.g., The detective didn’t find some guys). Recent studies suggest that, although children are capable of accessing inverse scope interpretations of such sentences, they resort to surface scope to a larger extent than adults. To account for children’s behavioral pattern, we propose a new factor at play in Truth Value Judgment tasks: the Question–Answer Requirement (QAR). According to the QAR, children (and adults) must interpret the target sentence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Dynamic predicate logic.Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stokhof - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (1):39-100.
    This paper is devoted to the formulation and investigation of a dynamic semantic interpretation of the language of first-order predicate logic. The resulting system, which will be referred to as ‘dynamic predicate logic’, is intended as a first step towards a compositional, non-representational theory of discourse semantics. In the last decade, various theories of discourse semantics have emerged within the paradigm of model-theoretic semantics. A common feature of these theories is a tendency to do away with the principle of compositionality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   350 citations  
  • Donkey business.Bart Geurts - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (2):129-156.
    In this paper I present experimental data showing that the interpretation of donkey sentences is influenced by certain aspects of world knowledge that seem to elude introspective observation, which I try to explain by reference to a scale ranging from prototypical individuals (like children) to quite marginal ones (such as railway lines). This ontological cline interacts with the semantics of donkey sentences: as suggested already by the anecdotal data on which much of the literature is based, the effect of world (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Intensional and higher-order modal logic: with applications to Montague semantics.Daniel Gallin - 1975 - New York: American Elsevier Pub. Co..
    CHAPTER 1. INTENSIONAL LOGIC §1. Natural Language and Intensional Logic When we speak of a theory of meaning for a natural language such as English, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Intensional and Higher-Order Modal Logic, with Applications to Montague Semantics.Kenneth A. Bowen - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (4):581-583.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Vagueness, truth and logic.Kit Fine - 1975 - Synthese 30 (3-4):265-300.
    This paper deals with the truth-Conditions and the logic for vague languages. The use of supervaluations and of classical logic is defended; and other approaches are criticized. The truth-Conditions are extended to a language that contains a definitely-Operator and that is subject to higher order vagueness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   647 citations  
  • Anaphora and dynamic binding.Gennaro Chierchia - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (2):111--183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Plurals, all, and the nonuniformity of collective predication.C. Brisson - 2003 - Linguistics and Philosophy 26 (2):129-184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Donkey pluralities: plural information states versus non-atomic individuals.Adrian Brasoveanu - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (2):129-209.
    The paper argues that two distinct and independent notions of plurality are involved in natural language anaphora and quantification: plural reference (the usual non-atomic individuals) and plural discourse reference, i.e., reference to a quantificational dependency between sets of objects (e.g., atomic/non-atomic individuals) that is established and subsequently elaborated upon in discourse. Following van den Berg (PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam, 1996), plural discourse reference is modeled as plural information states (i.e., as sets of variable assignments) in a new dynamic system (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Presuppositions for proportional quantifiers.Chris Barker - 1996 - Natural Language Semantics 4 (3):237-259.
    Most studies of the so-called proportion problem seek to understand how lexical and structural properties of sentences containing adverbial quantifiers give rise to various proportional readings. This paper explores a related but distinct problem: given a use of a particular sentence in context, why do only some of the expected proportional readings seem to be available? That is, why do some sentences allow an asymmetric reading when other, structurally similar sentences seem to require a symmetric reading? Potential factors suggested in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Generalized quantifiers and natural language.John Barwise & Robin Cooper - 1981 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2):159--219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   595 citations  
  • CWI Tract.Theo M. V. Janssen - 1986
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Dynamics of meaning: anaphora, presupposition, and the theory of grammar.Gennaro Chierchia - 1995 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    In The Dynamics of Meaning , Gennaro Chierchia tackles central issues in dynamic semantics and extends the general framework. Chapter 1 introduces the notion of dynamic semantics and discusses in detail the phenomena that have been used to motivate it, such as "donkey" sentences and adverbs of quantification. The second chapter explores in greater depth the interpretation of indefinites and issues related to presuppositions of uniqueness and the "E-type strategy." In Chapter 3, Chierchia extends the dynamic approach to the domain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Presumptive meanings: the theory of generalized conversational implicature.Stephen C. Levinson - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    When we speak, we mean more than we say. In this book Stephen C. Levinson explains some general processes that underlie presumptions in communication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   429 citations  
  • The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases.Irene Heim - 1982 - Dissertation, Umass Amherst
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   593 citations  
  • Anaphora.Jeffrey C. King & Karen S. Lewis - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Information Structure in Discourse: Towards an Integrated Formal Theory of Pragmatics.Craige Roberts - 1996 - Semantics and Pragmatics 5:1-69.
    A framework for pragmatic analysis is proposed which treats discourse as a game, with context as a scoreboard organized around the questions under discussion by the interlocutors. The framework is intended to be coordinated with a dynamic compositional semantics. Accordingly, the context of utterance is modeled as a tuple of different types of information, and the questions therein — modeled, as is usual in formal semantics, as alternative sets of propositions — constrain the felicitous flow of discourse. A requirement of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   268 citations  
  • Scorekeeping in a Language Game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (3):339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   622 citations  
  • Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences.Manfred Krifka - unknown
    The classical analysis of donkey sentences like (1.a,b) in Kamp (1981) and Heim (1982) assigns them truth conditions as given in (2.a). That is, they are treated as quantifications over farmer-donkey pairs. Partee (1984) and Kadmon (1987) have pointed out that the proper reading of (1.b), and a preferred reading of (1.a), is rather a quantification over farmers, as illustrated in (2.b).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Anaphora and the logic of change.Reinhard Muskens - 1991 - In Jan Van Eijck (ed.), Logics in AI, Proceedings of JELIA '90, volume 478 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. pp. 412-427.
    This paper shows how the dynamic interpretation of natural language introduced in work by Hans Kamp and Irene Heim can be modeled in classical type logic. This provides a synthesis between Richard Montague's theory of natural language semantics and the work by Kamp and Heim.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Tense and the logic of change.Reinhard Muskens - 1995 - In Urs Egli, Peter Pause, Christoph Schwarze, Arnim von Stechow & Götz Wienold (eds.), Lexical Knowledge in the Organization of Language. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. pp. 147-183.
    In this paper it is shown how the DRT (Discourse Representation Theory) treatment of temporal anaphora can be formalized within a version of Montague Semantics that is based on classical type logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • An Antinomy about Anaphora.Mahrad Almotahari - 2011 - Linguistic Inquiry 42 (3):509-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Presuppositions: Supervaluations and Free Logic.B. C. van Fraassen - 1969 - In K. Lambert (ed.), The Logical Way of Doing Things. Yale University Press. pp. 67-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Scalar implicature as a grammatical phenomenon.Gennaro Chierchia, Danny Fox & Benjamin Spector - 2012 - In Klaus von Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn & Paul Portner (eds.), Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning. De Gruyter Mouton. pp. 3--2297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Pronouns as paraphrases.Terence Parsons - 1978
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Negative Polarity, Definites Under Quantification and General Statements.Eric Griffin Jackson - 1994 - Dissertation, Stanford University
    This dissertation is concerned with two problems in semantics that have attracted a great deal of attention: negative polarity items and donkey sentences. "Any", as it occurs in is a negative polarity item, while the sentence in is a donkey sentence: Mary doesn't have any apples. Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. ;The problem posed by negative polarity items is to account for their distribution, while that posed by donkey sentences is to explain the interpretations they get in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations