Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Real Problem with Uniqueness

SATS 18 (2):125-139 (2017)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Mathematical logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1951 - Cambridge,: Harvard University Press.
    INTRODUCTION MATHEMATICAL logic differs from the traditional formal logic so markedly in method, and so far surpasses it in power and subtlety, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • Linguistics in Philosophy.Zeno Vendler - 1967 - Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press.
    This book is a major attempt to reconcile the empirical basis of linguistic science with the a priori nature of philosophical reasoning. Its purpose is to show how the methods and findings of linguistic science, especially of transformational grammar, can be used to cast light upon central problems of analytic philosophy. After dealing with recent objections to the use of linguistic techniques in philosophy, the author shows, with great force and clarity, how these techniques can be applied to such problems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • The Loss of Uniqueness.Z. Gendler Szabo - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1185-1222.
    Philosophers and linguists alike tend to call a semantic theory ‘Russellian’ just in case it assigns to sentences in which definite descriptions occur the truth-conditions Russell did in ‘On Denoting’. This is unfortunate; not all aspects of those particular truth-conditions do explanatory work in Russell's writings. As far as the semantics of descriptions is concerned, the key insights of ‘On Denoting’ are that definite descriptions are not uniformly referring expressions, and that they are scope-bearing elements. Anyone who accepts these two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The loss of uniqueness.Szabó Zoltán Gendler - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1185 - 1222.
    Philosophers and linguists alike tend to call a semantic theory ‘Russellian’ just in case it assigns to sentences in which definite descriptions occur the truth-conditions Russell did in ‘On Denoting’. This is unfortunate; not all aspects of those particular truth-conditions do explanatory work in Russell's writings. As far as the semantics of descriptions is concerned, the key insights of ‘On Denoting’ are that definite descriptions are not uniformly referring expressions, and that they are scope-bearing elements. Anyone who accepts these two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Loss of Uniqueness.ZoltÁ Gendler SzabÓ - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1185-1222.
    Philosophers and linguists alike tend to call a semantic theory 'Russellian' just in case it assigns to sentences in which definite descriptions occur the truth-conditions Russell did in 'On Denoting'. This is unfortunate; not all aspects of those particular truth-conditions do explanatory work in Russell's writings. As far as the semantics of descriptions is concerned, the key insights of 'On Denoting' are that definite descriptions are not uniformly referring expressions, and that they are scope-bearing elements. Anyone who accepts these two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Descriptions and uniqueness.Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 101 (1):29-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • On referring.Peter F. Strawson - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):320-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   614 citations  
  • Identifying reference and truth-values.P. F. Strawson - 1964 - Theoria 30 (2):96-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • On Quantifier Domain Restriction.Jason Stanley & Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):219--61.
    In this paper, we provide a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but our own proposal. Among the many accounts we consider and reject are the ‘explicit’ approach to quantifier domain restric‐tion discussed, for example, by Stephen Neale, and the pragmatic approach to quantifier domain restriction proposed by Kent Bach. Our hope is that the exhaustive discussion of this special case of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • Incomplete Definite Descriptions.Scott Soames - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (3):349--375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Ghosts, Murderers, and the Semantics of Descriptions.Anders Johan Schoubye - 2011 - Noûs 47 (3):496-533.
    It is widely agreed that sentences containing a non-denoting description embedded in the scope of a propositional attitude verb have true de dicto interpretations, and Russell's (1905) analysis of definite descriptions is often praised for its simple analysis of such cases, cf. e.g. Neale (1990). However, several people, incl. Elbourne (2005, 2009), Heim (1991), and Kripke (2005), have contested this by arguing that Russell's analysis yields incorrect predictions in non-doxastic attitude contexts. Heim and Elbourne have subsequently argued that once certain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Descriptions, truth value intuitions, and questions.Anders J. Schoubye - 2009 - Linguistics and Philosophy 32 (6):583-617.
    Since the famous debate between Russell (Mind 14: 479–493, 1905, Mind 66: 385–389, 1957) and Strawson (Mind 59: 320–344, 1950; Introduction to logical theory, 1952; Theoria, 30: 96–118, 1964) linguistic intuitions about truth values have been considered notoriously unreliable as a guide to the semantics of definite descriptions. As a result, most existing semantic analyses of definites leave a large number of intuitions unexplained. In this paper, I explore the nature of the relationship between truth value intuitions and non-referring definites. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Descriptions, indexicals, and belief reports: Some dilemmas (but not the ones you expect).Stephen Schiffer - 1995 - Mind 104 (413):107-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Russell.R. M. Sainsbury - 1979 - New York: Routledge.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Russell.Simon Blackburn - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (121):359-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mr. Strawson on referring.Bertrand Russell - 1957 - Mind 66 (263):385-389.
    Leaving detail aside, I think we may sum up Mr. Strawson's argument and my reply to it as follows: There are two problems, that of descriptions and that of egocentricity. Mr. Strawson thinks they are one and the same problem, but it is obvious from his discussion that he has not considered as many kinds of descriptive phrases as are relevant to the argument. Having confused the two problems, he asserts dogmatically that it is only the egocentric problem that needs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Quantification and context.Marga Reimer - 1998 - Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (1):95-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Literal Meaning. [REVIEW]Kent Bach - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2):487-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   292 citations  
  • Literal Meaning.François Récanati - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    According to the dominant position among philosophers of language today, we can legitimately ascribe determinate contents to natural language sentences, independently of what the speaker actually means. This view contrasts with that held by ordinary language philosophers fifty years ago: according to them, speech acts, not sentences, are the primary bearers of content. François Recanati argues for the relevance of this controversy to the current debate about semantics and pragmatics. Is 'what is said' determined by linguistic conventions, or is it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   504 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought.François Récanati - 1993 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    This volume puts forward a distinct new theory of direct reference, blending insights from both the Fregean and the Russellian traditions, and fitting the general theory of language understanding used by those working on the pragmatics of natural language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   240 citations  
  • Bach on behalf of Russell.M. Ramachandran - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):283-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bach on Behalf of Russell.Murali Ramachandran - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):283 - 287.
    An utterance of a sentence involving an incomplete (definite) description, ‘the F’, where the context—even taking the speaker’s intentions into account—does not determine a unique F, would be unintelligible. But an utterance (in the same context) of the corresponding Russellian paraphrase would not be unintelligible. So I urged in ‘A Strawsonian objection to Russell’s theory of descriptions’ (ANALYSIS 53, 1993, pp. 209-12). I compared an utterance of (1) The table is covered with books. with an utterance of (1)’s Russellian paraphrase..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Strawsonian Objection to Russell’s Theory of Descriptions.Murali Ramachandran - 1993 - Analysis 53 (4):209 - 212.
    One of Strawson's objections to Russell's theory of descriptions is that what are intuitively natural and correct utterances of sentences involving incomplete descriptions come out false by RTD. Russellians have responded, not by challenging Strawson's view that these uses are natural and correct, but by embellishing RTD to accommodate these uses. I pursue an alternative line of attack: I argue that there are circumstances in which "we" would find utterances of such sentences unnatural and improper but "RTD" would sanction. So, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic. [REVIEW]E. N. & Willard Van Orman Quine - 1940 - Journal of Philosophy 37 (23):640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • On being explicit comments on Stanley and Szabo, and on Bach.Stephen Neale - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):284–294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Descriptions.D. E. Over - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172):392-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Russell’s Notion of Scope.Saul A. Kripke - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1005-1037.
    Despite the renown of ‘On Denoting’, much criticism has ignored or misconstrued Russell's treatment of scope, particularly in intensional, but also in extensional contexts. This has been rectified by more recent commentators, yet it remains largely unnoticed that the examples Russell gives of scope distinctions are questionable or inconsistent with his own philosophy. Nevertheless, Russell is right: scope does matter in intensional contexts. In Principia Mathematica, Russell proves a metatheorem to the effect that the scope of a single occurrence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Thought and Reference.Bernard W. Kobes - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Context Dependence and Compositionality.Pelletier Francis Jeffry - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (2):148–161.
    Some utterances of sentences such as ‘Every student failed the midterm exam’ and ‘There is no beer’ are widely held to be true in a conversation despite the facts that not every student in the world failed the midterm exam and that there is, in fact, some beer somewhere. For instance, the speaker might be talking about some particular course, or about his refrigerator. Stanley and Szabó (in Mind and Language v. 15, 2000) consider many different approaches to how contextual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What Russell Couldn't Describe.Fredrik Haraldsen - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (3):459-473.
    The characteristic property of definite descriptions in natural language is commonly assumed to be their uniqueness requirement, although there is disagreement with respect to how occurrences should be interpreted, for instance with regard to the well-known restriction problem. I offer a novel argument against characterizing definite expressions in terms of uniqueness. If a singular definite description ?the F? implies that its denotation is the unique satisfier of ?F? (relative to a context) then there are real-life states of affairs that can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Contextually Incomplete Descriptions: A New Counterexample to Russell?Jonardon Ganeri - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):287 - 290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contextually Incomplete Descriptions: A New Counterexample to Russell?Jonardon Ganeri - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought.Jennifer M. Saul - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   193 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Meaning, quantification, necessity: themes in philosophical logic.Martin Davies - 1981 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Situations and Attitudes.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   274 citations  
  • Has the problem of incompleteness rested on a mistake?Ray Buchanan & Gary Ostertag - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):889-913.
    A common objection to Russell's theory of descriptions concerns incomplete definite descriptions: uses of (for example) ‘the book is overdue’ in contexts where there is clearly more than one book. Many contemporary Russellians hold that such utterances will invariably convey a contextually determined complete proposition, for example, that the book in your briefcase is overdue. But according to the objection this gets things wrong: typically, when a speaker utters such a sentence, no facts about the context or the speaker's communicative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Wettstein on definite descriptions.William K. Blackburn - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (2):263 - 278.
    I critically examine an argument, due to howard wettstein, purporting to show that sentences containing definite descriptions are semantically ambiguous between referential and attributive readings. Wettstein argues that many sentences containing nonidentifying descriptions--descriptions that apply to more than one object--cannot be given a Russellian analysis, and that the descriptions in these sentences should be understood as directly referential terms. But because Wettstein does not justify treating referential uses of nonidentifying descriptions differently than attributive uses of nonidentifying descriptions, his argument fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Pragmatics, semantic undetermination and the referential/attributive distinction.A. Bezuidenhout - 1997 - Mind 106 (423):375-409.
    It has long ben recognised that there are referential uses of definite descriptions. It is not as widely recognised that there are atttributives uses of idexicals and other such paradigmatically singular terms. I offer an account of the referential/attributive distinction which is intended to give a unified treatment of both sorts of cases. I argue that the best way to account for the referential/attributive distinction is to treat is as semantically underdetermined which sort of propositions is expressed in a context. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Situations and Attitudes.Jon Barwise - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (11):668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Situations and attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (11):668-691.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   580 citations  
  • Situations and Attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1983 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Edited by John Perry.
    This volume tackles the slippery subject of 'meaning'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • Ramachandran vs. Russell.Kent Bach - 1994 - Analysis 54 (3):183 - 186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Quantification, qualification and context a reply to Stanley and Szabó.Kent Bach - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):262–283.
    We hardly ever mean exactly what we say. I don’t mean that we generally speak figuratively or that we’re generally insincere. Rather, I mean that we generally speak loosely, omitting words that could have made what we meant more explicit and letting our audience fill in the gaps. Language works far more efficiently when we do that. Literalism can have its virtues, as when we’re drawing up a contract, programming a computer, or writing a philosophy paper, but we generally opt (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Truth-Conditional Pragmatics.François Recanati - 2010 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues against the traditional understanding of the semantics/pragmatics divide and puts forward a radical alternative. Through half a dozen case studies, it shows that what an utterance says cannot be neatly separated from what the speaker means. In particular, the speaker's meaning endows words with senses that are tailored to the situation of utterance and depart from the conventional meanings carried by the words in isolation. This phenomenon of ‘pragmatic modulation’ must be taken into account in theorizing about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • The Myth of Semantic Presupposition.Steven E. Boer & William G. Lycan - 1976 - Indiana University Linguistics Club.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. [REVIEW]Stephen Schiffer - 1996 - Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (1):91-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. [REVIEW]Kenneth Taylor - 1997 - Noûs 31 (4):538-556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Definite Descriptions.Paul Elbourne - 2013 - Oxford University Press.
    Paul Elbourne defends the Fregean view that definite descriptions ('the table', 'the King of France') refer to individuals, and offers a new and radical account of the semantics of pronouns. He draws on a wide range of work, from Frege, Peano, and Russell to the latest findings in linguistics, philosophy of language, and psycholinguistics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Relevance: Communication and Cognition.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 1986/1995 - Oxford: Blackwell.
    This revised edition includes a new Preface outlining developments in Relevance Theory since 1986, discussing the more serious criticisms of the theory, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1170 citations