Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Defense of Presentism.Ned Markosian - 2004 - Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1:47-82.
    ∗ Apologies to Mark Hinchliff for stealing the title of his dissertation. (See Hinchliff, A Defense of Presentism. As it turns out, however, the version of Presentism defended here is different from the version defended by Hinchliff. See Section 3.1 below.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • Sense and Sensibilia.[author unknown] - 1962 - Foundations of Language 3 (3):303-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • A Defense of Presentism.Ned Markosian - 2004 - In Dean Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 1. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • Time, Tense and Causation.Quentin Smith & Michael Tooley - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (1):123.
    The main goal of Michael Tooley’s groundbreaking book is to establish a position intermediate between the tenseless theory of time and the standard tensed theory of time. Tooley argues for a novel version of the tensed theory of time, namely, that the future is unreal and the present and past real, and yet that reality consists only of tenseless facts. The question that naturally arises for the reader concerns an apparent paradox: how could the tensed theory of time be true (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • A neglected account of perception.Tom Stoneham - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (3):307-322.
    I aim to draw the reader's attention to an easily overlooked account of perception, namely that there are no perceptual experiences, that to perceive something is to stand in an external, purely non-Leibnizian relation to it. I introduce the Purely Relational account of perception by discussing a case of it being overlooked in the writings of G.E. Moore, though we also find the same move in J. Cook Wilson, so it has nothing to do with an affection for sense-data. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The admissible contents of visual experience.Michael Tye - 2009 - Philosophical Quarterly 59 (236):541-562.
    My purpose is to take a close look at the nature of visual content. I discuss the view that visual experiences have only existential contents, the view that visual experiences have either singular or gappy contents, and the view that visual experiences have multiple contents. I also consider a proposal about visual content inspired by Kaplan's well known theory of indexicals. I draw out some consequences of my discussion for the thesis of intentionalism with respect to the phenomenal character of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The silence of the senses.Charles Travis - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):57-94.
    There is a view abroad on which perceptual experience has representational content in this sense: in it something is represented to the perceiver as so. On the view, a perceptual experience has a face value at which it may be taken, or which may be rejected. This paper argues that that view is mistaken: there is nothing in perceptual experience which makes it so that in it anything is represented as so. In that sense, the senses are silent, or, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   334 citations  
  • Perception and the time-gap argument.W. A. Suchting - 1969 - Philosophical Quarterly 19 (January):46-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Lectures on Philosophy.Barry Stroud, G. E. Moore & Casimir Lewy - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (3):420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • XI*—Perception, Vision and Causation.Paul Snowdon - 1981 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81 (1):175-192.
    Paul Snowdon; XI*—Perception, Vision and Causation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 175–192, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • The Objects of Perceptual Experience.Paul Snowdon & Howard Robinson - 1990 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 64 (1):121-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • The formulation of disjunctivism: A response to fish.Paul F. Snowdon - 2005 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1):129-141.
    Fish proposes that we need to elucidate what 'disjunctivism' stands for, and he also proposes that it stands for the rejection of a principle about the nature of experience that he calls the decisiveness principle. The present paper argues that his first proposal is reasonable, but then argues, in Section II, that his positive suggestion does not draw the line between disjunctivism and non-disjunctivism in the right place. In Section III, it is argued that disjunctivism is a thesis about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Some Reflections on an Argument from Hallucination.Paul F. Snowdon - 2005 - Philosophical Topics 33 (1):285-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Perception, vision, and causation.Paul Snowdon - 1981 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81:175-92.
    Paul Snowdon; XI*—Perception, Vision and Causation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 175–192, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Philosophy and Scientific Realism.J. J. C. Smart - 1965\ - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15 (60):358-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations  
  • Substance.Bertrand Russell - 1927 - Humana Mente 2 (5):20-27.
    The question of substance in the philosophy of physics has three branches: logical, physical, and epistemological. The first is a problem in pure philosophy: is the notion of “ substance ” in any sense a “ category,” i.e. forced upon us by the general nature either of facts or of knowledge? The second is a question of the interpretation of mathematical physics: is it necessary, or convenient to interpret our formulae in terms of permanent entities with changing states and relations? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Perception: A Representative Theory.Stephanie A. Ross - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (4):623.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Perception.Howard Robinson - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (188):382-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Perception.Howard Robinson - 1994 - Philosophy 70 (273):463-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Do mental events have durations?Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):277-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The Sense-Datum Fallacy.H. A. Prighard - 1938 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 17 (1):1-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Perceiving External Things and the Time‐Lag Argument.Sean Enda Power - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):94-117.
    We seem to directly perceive external things. But can we? According to the time‐lag argument, we cannot. What we directly perceive happens now. There is a time‐lag between our perceptions and the external things we seem to directly perceive; these external things happen in the past; thus, what we directly perceive must be something else, for example, sense‐data, and we can only at best indirectly perceive other things. This paper examines the time‐lag argument given contemporary metaphysics. I argue that this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Theory of Perception.W. Preston Warren - 1972 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 33 (1):136-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • XI*—Seeing the Light.Brian O'Shaughnessy - 1985 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 85 (1):193-218.
    Brian O'Shaughnessy; XI*—Seeing the Light, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 85, Issue 1, 1 June 1985, Pages 193–218, https://doi.org/10.1093/aris.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Seeing the Light.Brian O'Shaughnessy - 1985 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 85:193 - 218.
    Brian O'Shaughnessy; XI*—Seeing the Light, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 85, Issue 1, 1 June 1985, Pages 193–218, https://doi.org/10.1093/aris.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Experience of the world in time.Alva Noe - 2006 - Analysis 66 (1):26-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Experience of the world in time.Alva NoË - 2006 - Analysis 66 (289):26-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Perception and the 'time-lag' argument.Gerald E. Myers - 1957 - Analysis 17 (April):97-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Naïve Realism, Hallucination, and Causation: A New Response to the Screening Off Problem.Alex Moran - 2019 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):368-382.
    This paper sets out a novel response to the ‘screening off problem’ for naïve realism. The aim is to resist the claim (which many naïve realists accept) that the kind of experience involved in hallucinating also occurs during perception, by arguing that there are causal constraints that must be met if an hallucinatory experience is to occur that are never met in perceptual cases. Notably, given this response, it turns out that, contra current orthodoxy, naïve realists need not adopt any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The limits of self-awareness.Michael G. F. Martin - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 120 (1-3):37-89.
    The disjunctive theory of perception claims that we should understand statements about how things appear to a perceiver to be equivalent to statements of a disjunction that either one is perceiving such and such or one is suffering an illusion (or hallucination); and that such statements are not to be viewed as introducing a report of a distinctive mental event or state common to these various disjoint situations. When Michael Hinton first introduced the idea, he suggested that the burden of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  • Veridical hallucination and prosthetic vision.David Lewis - 1980 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (3):239-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  • Putnam’s paradox.David Lewis - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):221 – 236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   408 citations  
  • Sense-Perception and Matter; a Critical Analysis of C. D. Broad's Theory of Perception. [REVIEW]A. G. Ramsperger - 1955 - Journal of Philosophy 52 (2):51-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Disjunctivism Unmotivated.Gordon Knight - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences (2):1-18.
    Many naive realists endorse a negative disjunctivist strategy in order to deal with the challenge presented by the possibility of phenomenologically indistinguishable halucination. In the first part of this paper I argue that this approach is methodologically inconsistent because it undercuts the phenomenological motivation that underlies the the appeal of naive realism. In the second part of the paper I develop an alternative to the negative disjunctivist account along broadly Meinongian lines. In the last section of this paper I consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Disjunctivism unmotivated.Gordon Knight - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (2):355-372.
    Many naive realists are inclined to accept a negative disjunctivist strategy in order to deal with the challenge presented by the possibility of phenomenologically indistinguishable hallucination. In the first part of this paper I argue that this approach is methodologically inconsistent because it undercuts the phenomenological motivation that underlies the appeal of naive realism. In the second part of the paper I develop an alternative to the negative disjunctivist account along broadly Meinongian lines. In the last section of this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Perception.S. Kerby-Miller - 1935 - Philosophical Review 44 (2):192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • The Multiply Qualitative.Mark Eli Kalderon - 2011 - Mind 120 (478):239-262.
    Shoemaker argues that one could not hold both that the qualitative character of colour experience is inherited from the qualitative character of the experienced colour and that there are faultless forms of variation in colour perception. In this paper, I explain what is meant by inheritance and discuss in detail the problematic cases of perceptual variation. In so doing I argue that these claims are in fact consistent, and that the appearance to the contrary is due to an optional and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Color Illusion.Mark Eli Kalderon - 2011 - Noûs 45 (4):751-775.
    As standardly conceived, an illusion is an experience of an object o appearing F where o is not in fact F. Paradigm examples of color illusion, however, do not fit this pattern. A diagnosis of this uncovers different sense of appearance talk that is the basis of a dilemma for the standard conception. The dilemma is only a challenge. But if the challenge cannot be met, then any conception of experience, such as representationalism, that is committed to the standard conception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The obscure object of hallucination.Mark Johnston - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 120 (1-3):113-83.
    Like dreaming, hallucination has been a formative trope for modern philosophy. The vivid, often tragic, breakdown in the mind’s apparent capacity to disclose reality has long served to support a paradoxical philosophical picture of sensory experience. This picture, which of late has shaped the paradigmatic empirical understanding the senses, displays sensory acts as already complete without the external world; complete in that the direct objects even of veridical sensory acts do not transcend what we could anyway hallucinate. Hallucination is thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   252 citations  
  • There are no visual fields (and no minds either).Mark Johnston - 2011 - Analytic Philosophy 52 (4):231-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Objective Mind and the Objectivity of Our Minds.Mark Johnston - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2):233-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Why so Serious? Non-serious Presentism and the Problem of Cross-temporal Relations.Ross Inman - 2012 - Metaphysica 13 (1):55-63.
    It is a common assumption in the metaphysics of time that a commitment to presentism entails a commitment to serious presentism, the view that objects can exemplify properties or stand in relations only at times at which they exist. As a result, non-serious presentism is widely thought to be beyond the bounds for the card-carrying presentist in response to the problem of cross-temporal relations. In this paper, I challenge this general consensus by examining one common argument in favor of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Some implications of the time-lag argument.Ronald W. Houts - 1980 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 41 (1/2):150-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Problems of Perception.R. J. Hirst - 1959 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 150:542-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The identity of the past.Mark Hinchliff - 2010 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds.), Time and Identity. MIT Press. pp. 95--110.
    This chapter discusses the obstacles faced by presentists after denying the existence of past and future individuals. Presentism must still account for the manifest facts about the past and the future, but problems may arise when the presentist attempts to provide an account of the past. There is nothing in the presentist’s ontology on which to base truths about the past. Also, there is a problem regarding singular truths about past individuals; if past individuals do not exist, then they do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Ordinary language, common sense, and the time-lag argument.Richard G. Henson - 1967 - Mind 76 (301):21-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Disjunctivism.John Hawthorne & Karson Kovakovich - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):145-83.
    [John Hawthorne] We examine some well-known disjunctivist projects in the philosophy of perception, mainly in a critical vein. Our discussion is divided into four parts. Following some introductory remarks, we examine in part two the link between object-dependent contents and disjunctivism. In part three, we explore the disjunctivist's use of discriminability facts as a basis for understanding experience. In part four, we examine an interesting argument for disjunctivism that has been offered by Michael Martin. /// [Scott Sturgeon] The paper aims (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Naive Realist Perspectives on Seeing Blurrily.Craig French - 2014 - Ratio 27 (4):393-413.
    Naive realists hold that experience is to be understood in terms of an intimate perceptual relation between a subject and aspects of the world, relative to a certain standpoint. Those aspects of the world themselves shape the contours of consciousness. But blurriness is an aspect of some of our experiences that does not seem to come from the world. I argue that this constitutes a significant challenge to some forms of naive realism. But I also argue that there is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Philosophy of perception: a contemporary introduction.William Fish (ed.) - 2010 - New York: Routledge.
    Introduction: Three key principles -- Sense datum theories -- Adverbial theories -- Belief acquisition theories -- Intentional theories -- Disjunctive theories -- Perception and causation -- Perception and the sciences of the mind -- Perception and other sense modalities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Perception and the Time-Lag Argument.G. E. Myers - 1956 - Analysis 17 (5):97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations