Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A metaphysics for the mob: the philosophy of George Berkeley.John Russell Roberts - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    George Berkeley notoriously claimed that his immaterialist metaphysics was not only consistent with common sense but that it was also integral to its defense. Roberts argues that understanding the basic connection between Berkeley's philosophy and common sense requires that we develop a better understanding of the four principle components of Berkeley's positive metaphysics: The nature of being, the divine language thesis, the active/passive distinction, and the nature of spirits. Roberts begins by focusing on Berkeley's view of the nature of being. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Berkeley's Principles of human knowledge: a reader's guide.Alasdair Richmond - 2009 - New York: Continuum.
    Note on the text of the principles -- Context -- Biography -- Berkeley's philosophical background -- Overview of themes -- Teading the text -- The principles : introduction -- The principles : part one -- The objects and subject of knowledge : ideas and spirit -- Unperceived existence : a nicer strain of abstraction -- Problems for materialism -- A Cartesian dream argument -- The master argument -- From the inertness of ideas to the existence of God -- Philosophical objections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Berkeley on Doing Good and Meaning Well.Hugh Hunter - 2015 - In Sébastien Charles (ed.), Berkeley Revisited: Moral, Social and Political Philosophy. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation. pp. 131-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vulgar Thoughts: Berkeley on Responsibility and Freedom.Timo Airaksinen - 2015 - In Sébastien Charles (ed.), Berkeley Revisited: Moral, Social and Political Philosophy. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation. pp. 115-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Action and inaction in Berkeley.C. C. W. Taylor - 1985 - In John Foster & Howard Robinson (eds.), Essays on Berkeley: a tercentennial celebration. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Berkeley and Malebranche: a study in the origins of Berkeley's thought.Arthur Aston Luce - 1934 - New York: Garland.
    We are republishing these classic works in affordable, high quality, modern editions, using the original text and artwork.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Berkeley and the Microworld.Catherine Wilson - 1994 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1):37-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Action, knowledge and embodiment in Berkeley and Locke.Tom Stoneham - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations 21 (1):41-59.
    Embodiment is a fact of human existence which philosophers should not ignore. They may differ to a great extent in what they have to say about our bodies, but they have to take into account that for each of us our body has a special status, it is not merely one amongst the physical objects, but a physical object to which we have a unique relation. While Descartes approached the issue of embodiment through consideration of sensation and imagination, it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Introduction.John A. Robertson - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (2):175-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Berkeley, human agency and divine concurrentism.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (4):pp. 567-590.
    This paper aims to offer a sympathetic reading of Berkeley’s often maligned account of human agency. The first section briefly revisits three options concerning the relationship between human and divine agency available to theistically minded philosophers in the medieval and early modern eras. The second argues that, of those three views, only the position of concurrentism is consistent with Berkeley’s texts. The third section explores Berkeley’s reasons for adopting concurrentism by highlighting three motivating considerations drawn from his larger philosophical system. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Berkeley on the Activity of Spirits.Sukjae Lee - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (3):539-576.
    This paper propounds a new reading of Berkeley's account of the activity of finite spirits. Against existing interpretations, the paper argues that Berkeley does not hold that we causally contribute to the movement of our bodies. In contrast, our volitions to move our bodies are but occasions for God to cause their movement. In answer to the question of wherein then consists our activity, the paper proposes that our activity consists in the dual powers to produce (1) our volitions ? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The return to Berkeley.Jenny Keefe - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (1):101 – 113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction.John A. Robertson - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (2):175-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Salving the phenomena of mind: energy, hegemonikon, and sympathy in Cudworth.Sarah Hutton - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (3):465-486.
    Ralph Cudworth’s theory of mind was the most fully developed philosophical psychology among the Cambridge Platonists. Like his seventeenth-century contemporaries, Cudworth discussed mental powers in terms of soul rather than mind and considered the function of the soul to be not merely intellectual, but vital and moral. Cudworth conceived the soul as a single self-determining unit which combined many powers. He developed this against a philosophical agenda set by Descartes and Hobbes. But he turned to ancient philosophy, especially the philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Peter Olivi's Rejection of God's Concurrence with Created Causes.Gloria Frost - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (4):655-679.
    The relationship between divine and created causality was widely discussed in medieval and early modern philosophy. Contemporary scholars of these discussions typically stake out three possible positions: occasionalism, concurrentism, and mere-conservationism. It is regularly claimed that virtually no medieval thinker adopted the final view which denies that God is an immediate active cause of creaturely actions. The main aim of this paper is to further understanding of the medieval causality debate, and particularly the mere-conservationist position, by analysing Peter John Olivi's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Medieval Aristotelianism and the Case against Secondary Causation in Nature.Alfred J. Freddoso - 1988 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Cornell Up. pp. 74-118.
    Central to the western theistic understanding of divine providence is the conviction that God is the sovereign Lord of nature. He created the physical universe and continually conserves it in existence. What's more, He is always and everywhere active in it by His power. The operations of nature, be they minute or catastrophic, commonplace or unprecedented, are the work of His hands, and without His constant causal influence none of them would or could occur.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • God’s General Concurrence with Secondary Causes.Alfred J. Freddoso - 1994 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68 (2):131-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • God's general concurrence with secondary causes: Why conservation is not enough.Alfred J. Freddoso - 1991 - Philosophical Perspectives 5:553-585.
    After an exposition of some key concepts in scholastic ontology, this paper examines four arguments presented by Francisco Suarez for the thesis, commonly held by Christian Aristotelians, that God's causal contribution to effects occurring in the ordinary course of nature goes beyond His merely conserving created substances along with their active and passive causal powers. The postulation of a further causal contribution, known as God's general concurrence (or general concourse), can be viewed as an attempt to accommodate an element of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Berkeley's pantheistic discourse.Stephen H. Daniel - 2001 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 49 (3):179-194.
    Berkeley's immaterialism has more in common with views developed by Henry More, the mathematician Joseph Raphson, John Toland, and Jonathan Edwards than those of thinkers with whom he is commonly associated (e.g., Malebranche and Locke). The key for recognizing their similarities lies in appreciating how they understand St. Paul's remark that in God "we live and move and have our being" as an invitation to think to God as the space of discourse in which minds and ideas are identified. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Le modèle occasionnaliste. Emergence et développement, au tournant des XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles.Jean-Christophe Bardout - 2002 - Quaestio 2 (1):461-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Perception and Action.M. R. Ayers - 1969 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 3:91-106.
    There is an ancient and ambiguous philosophical doctrine that perception is passive. This can mean that the mind contributes nothing to the content of our sensory experience: its power of perception is a mere receptivity. In this sense the principle has often been questioned, and is indeed doubtful on empirical grounds, given one reasonable interpretation of what it would be for the mind to make such a contribution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Responsibility From the Margins.David Shoemaker - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    David Shoemaker presents a new pluralistic theory of responsibility, based on the idea of quality of will. His approach is motivated by our ambivalence to real-life cases of marginal agency, such as those caused by clinical depression, dementia, scrupulosity, psychopathy, autism, intellectual disability, and poor formative circumstances. Our ambivalent responses suggest that such agents are responsible in some ways but not others. Shoemaker develops a theory to account for our ambivalence, via close examination of several categories of pancultural emotional responsibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   152 citations  
  • The querist.George Berkeley - 1735 - Arc Manor LLC.
    George Berkeley (1685 - 1753), also known as Bishop Berkeley, was a philosopher. His primary philosophical achievement was the advancement of a theory he called "immaterialism" (later referred to as "subjective idealism" by others).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Berkeley's Argument for Other Minds.Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (4):431 - 440.
    The literature on Berkeley is almost unanimous in taking this claim to know the existence of other finite spirits to rest on an argument from analogy. I show that this is not so and that Berkeley uses a causal argument to prove that there are other minds. Questions of the degree to which it is legitimate for Berkeley to appeal to causes, particularly occasional causes, are addressed in the process.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Intentionality of Intentions.Annette C. Baier - 1977 - Review of Metaphysics 30 (3):389 - 414.
    Berkeley says that "the making and unmaking of ideas doth very properly denominate the mind active." What did Berkeley take as the paradigm of that making which denominates mind active? He speaks in the same passage of exciting "ideas in my mind at pleasure," of varying and shifting the scene "as oft as I see fit. It is no more than willing and straightway this or that idea arises in my fancy." This quite clearly takes human idea-making to be fantasizing. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Anthony Collins.William Uzgalis - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consequentialism.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 2019 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Nicolas Malebranche.Tad Schmaltz - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Stoicism.Dirk Baltzly - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Stoicism was one of the new philosophical movements of the Hellenistic period. The name derives from the porch (stoa poikilê) in the Agora at Athens decorated with mural paintings, where the members of the school congregated, and their lectures were held. Unlike ‘epicurean,’ the sense of the English adjective ‘stoical’ is not utterly misleading with regard to its philosophical origins. The Stoics did, in fact, hold that emotions like fear or envy (or impassioned sexual attachments, or passionate love of anything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Berkeley's notebooks.Robert McKim - 2005 - In Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. Cambridge University Press. pp. 63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On human liberty in Berkeley's Alciphron VII.Geneviève Brykman - 2008 - In Stephen Hartley Daniel (ed.), New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought. Humanity Books.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Berkeley's stoic notion of spiritual substance.Stephen H. Daniel - 2008 - In Stephen Hartley Daniel (ed.), New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought. Humanity Books.
    For Berkeley, minds are not Cartesian spiritual substances because they cannot be said to exist (even if only conceptually) abstracted from their activities. Similarly, Berkeley's notion of mind differs from Locke's in that, for Berkeley, minds are not abstract substrata in which ideas inhere. Instead, Berkeley redefines what it means for the mind to be a substance in a way consistent with the Stoic logic of 17th century Ramists on which Leibniz and Jonathan Edwards draw. This view of mind, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Berkeley on the Inward Evidence of Freedom.James Harris - 2010 - In Laurent Jaffro, Genevieve Brykman & Claire Schwartz (eds.), Berkeley's Alciphron: English Text and Essays in Interpretation. Georg Olms Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A New Approach to Berkeley's 'Philosophical Notebooks'.Bertil Belfrage - 1987 - In Ernest Sosa (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of George Berkeley. D. Reidel.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophical commentaries.George Berkeley, George H. Thomas, A. A. Luce & Wolfgang Breidert - 1980 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 170 (2):235-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Occasionalism and strict mechanism: Malebranche, Berkeley, fontenelle.Lisa Downing - 2005 - In Christia Mercer (ed.), Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 206-230.
    The rich connections between metaphysics and natural philosophy in the early modern period have been widely acknowledged and productively mined, thanks in no small part to the work of Margaret Wilson, whose book, Descartes, served as an inspirational example for a generation of scholars. The task of this paper is to investigate one particular such connection, namely, the relation between occasionalist metaphysics and strict mechanism. My focus will be on the work of Nicholas Malebranche, the most influential Cartesian philosopher after (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Descartes on Causation.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2006 - Studia Leibnitiana 38 (2):248-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Optimistic skepticism about free will.Derk Pereboom - 2013 - In Paul Russell & Oisin Deery (eds.), The Philosophy of Free Will: Essential Readings From the Contemporary Debates. Oup Usa. pp. 421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Introduction.Berman Berman - 1984 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 62:3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations