Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Space and Time in the Child’s Mind: Evidence for a Cross-Dimensional Asymmetry.Daniel Casasanto, Olga Fotakopoulou & Lera Boroditsky - 2010 - Cognitive Science 34 (3):387-405.
    What is the relationship between space and time in the human mind? Studies in adults show an asymmetric relationship between mental representations of these basic dimensions of experience: Representations of time depend on space more than representations of space depend on time. Here we investigated the relationship between space and time in the developing mind. Native Greek‐speaking children watched movies of two animals traveling along parallel paths for different distances or durations and judged the spatial and temporal aspects of these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Our knowledge of the external world: as a field for scientific method in philosophy.Bertrand Russell - 1914 - New York: Routledge.
    Philosophy, from the earliest times, has made greater claims, and achieved fewer results, than any other branch of learning. In Our Knowledge of the External World , Bertrand Russell illustrates instances where the claims of philosophers have been excessive, and examines why their achievements have not been greater.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Kant and the Capacity to Judge.Kenneth R. Westphal & Beatrice Longuenesse - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):645.
    Kant famously declares that “although all our cognition commences with experience, … it does not on that account all arise from experience”. This marks Kant’s disagreement with empiricism, and his contention that human knowledge and experience require both sensation and the use of certain a priori concepts, the Categories. However, this is only the surface of Kant’s much deeper, though neglected view about the nature of reason and judgment. Kant holds that even our a priori concepts are acquired, not from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   225 citations  
  • The logic of time: a model-theoretic investigation into the varieties of temporal ontology and temporal discourse.Johan van Benthem - 1991 - Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    The subject of Time has a wide intellectual appeal across different dis ciplines. This has shown in the variety of reactions received from readers of the first edition of the present Book. Many have reacted to issues raised in its philosophical discussions, while some have even solved a number of the open technical questions raised in the logical elaboration of the latter. These results will be recorded below, at a more convenient place. In the seven years after the first publication, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On constructing instants from events.S. K. Thomason - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (1):85 - 96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Free construction of time from events.S. K. Thomason - 1989 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 18 (1):43 - 67.
    Some may be of the opinion that one event can begin before another only by virtue of the existence of some event (a “witness”) which wholly precedes the other and does not wholly precede the one (and similarly for “ends before” and “does not abut”). Those would prefer $\mathbb{F}$ 0 to $\mathbb{F}$ as a model for observers' apprehensions of events. Since G is a functor from $\mathbb{M}$ to $\mathbb{F}$ 0, the current construction (restricted to $\mathbb{F}$ 0) remains applicable.This work supports (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):1-58.
    In his argument for the possibility of knowledge of spatial objects, in the Transcendental Deduction of the B-version of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant makes a crucial distinction between space as “form of intuition” and space as “formal intuition.” The traditional interpretation regards the distinction between the two notions as reflecting a distinction between indeterminate space and determinations of space by the understanding, respectively. By contrast, a recent influential reading has argued that the two notions can be fused into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On Order in Time.Bertrand Russell - 1936 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The pernicious influence of mathematics upon philosophy.Gian-Carlo Rota - 1991 - Synthese 88 (2):165 - 178.
    We shall argue that the attempt carried out by certain philosophers in this century to parrot the language, the method, and the results of mathematics has harmed philosophy. Such an attempt results from a misunderstanding of both mathematics and philosophy, and has harmed both subjects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Aristotelian Continuum. A Formal Characterization.Peter Roeper - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (2):211-232.
    While the classical account of the linear continuum takes it to be a totality of points, which are its ultimate parts, Aristotle conceives of it as continuous and infinitely divisible, without ultimate parts. A formal account of this conception can be given employing a theory of quantification for nonatomic domains and a theory of region-based topology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Immanuel Kant's mind and the brain's resting state.Georg Northoff - 2012 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (7):356-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Foundations of Geometry and Induction. [REVIEW]C. J. Ducasse - 1931 - Journal of Philosophy 28 (17):470-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Logic of Time. A Model-Theoretic Investigation into the Varieties of Temporal Antology and Temporal Discourse.Steven T. Kuhn & J. F. A. K. van Benthem - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):874.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Wilfrid Hodges - 1997 - Studia Logica 64 (1):133-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • The classical continuum without points.Geoffrey Hellman & Stewart Shapiro - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):488-512.
    We develop a point-free construction of the classical one- dimensional continuum, with an interval structure based on mereology and either a weak set theory or logic of plural quantification. In some respects this realizes ideas going back to Aristotle,although, unlike Aristotle, we make free use of classical "actual infinity". Also, in contrast to intuitionistic, Bishop, and smooth infinitesimal analysis, we follow classical analysis in allowing partitioning of our "gunky line" into mutually exclusive and exhaustive disjoint parts, thereby demonstrating the independence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant on geometry and spatial intuition.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):231-255.
    I use recent work on Kant and diagrammatic reasoning to develop a reconsideration of central aspects of Kant’s philosophy of geometry and its relation to spatial intuition. In particular, I reconsider in this light the relations between geometrical concepts and their schemata, and the relationship between pure and empirical intuition. I argue that diagrammatic interpretations of Kant’s theory of geometrical intuition can, at best, capture only part of what Kant’s conception involves and that, for example, they cannot explain why Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Time in the mind: Using space to think about time.Daniel Casasanto & Lera Boroditsky - 2008 - Cognition 106 (2):579-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • Newton's fluxions and equably flowing time.Richard T. W. Arthur - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (2):323-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A formalization of kant’s transcendental logic.Theodora Achourioti & Michiel van Lambalgen - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):254-289.
    Although Kant (1998) envisaged a prominent role for logic in the argumentative structure of his Critique of Pure Reason, logicians and philosophers have generally judged Kantgeneralformaltranscendental logics is a logic in the strict formal sense, albeit with a semantics and a definition of validity that are vastly more complex than that of first-order logic. The main technical application of the formalism developed here is a formal proof that Kants logic is after all a distinguished subsystem of first-order logic, namely what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Foundations of Geometry and Induction.Jean Nicod - 1930 - London, England: Routledge.
    First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Foundations of Geometry and Induction.Jean Nicod - 1930 - London, England: Routledge.
    First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Space, Time and Number in the Brain: Searching for the Foundations of Mathematical Thought.Stanislas Dehaene & Elizabeth Brannon (eds.) - 2011 - Oxford University Press.
    A uniquely integrative work, this volume provides a much needed compilation of primary source material to researchers from basic neuroscience, psychology, developmental science, neuroimaging, neuropsychology and theoretical biology. * The ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Kant's Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science.Michael Friedman - 2013 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science is one of the most difficult but also most important of Kant's works. Published in 1786 between the first and second editions of the Critique of Pure Reason, the Metaphysical Foundations occupies a central place in the development of Kant's philosophy, but has so far attracted relatively little attention compared with other works of Kant's critical period. Michael Friedman's book develops a new and complete reading of this work and reconstructs Kant's main argument clearly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy, by C. D. Broad. [REVIEW]Bertrand Russell - 1914 - International Journal of Ethics 25:259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Logic of Time: A Model-Theoretic Investigation into the Varieties of Temporal Ontology and Temporal Discourse.J. F. A. K. van Benthem - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (3):235-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Our Knowledge of the external World as a field of scientific method in Philosophy.Bertrand Russell - 1914 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 81:306-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Kant and the brain: A new empirical hypothesis.Linda Palmer - manuscript
    Immanuel Kant’s three great Critiques stand among the bulkier monuments of Enlightenment thought. The first is best known; the last had until recently been rather less studied. But his final Critique contains, I contend, a remarkable development of Kant’s theory of how human beings use and create systems of knowledge. While Kant was not himself concerned with the neuronal substrates of cognition, I argue this development yields a novel empirical hypothesis susceptible of experimental investigation. Here I present the Kantian motivation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Synthetic Differential Geometry.Anders Kock - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):244-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations