Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Articles on Aristotle: 1. Science. [REVIEW]Anthony Preus - 1976 - International Studies in Philosophy 8:222-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)On Aristotle's Conception of the Soul.Michael Frede - 1992 - In Martha C. Nussbaum & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's de Anima. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This essay explores Aristotle’s conception of the soul. Aristotle believes that natural objects and their behaviour cannot be fully understood in terms of their material constituents and their properties, but have to be explained in terms of their essence or nature. Souls are simply a particular kind of essence or nature, namely the essence or nature of animal bodies. Doing justice to physical or natural phenomena requires the notion of a form or nature. Once this notion is allowed, it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: A Moderate Interpretation of Aristotle’s De Memoria and De Anima on the Role of Images in Intellectual Activities.Caleb Cohoe - 2016 - Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy 61 (3):337-372.
    I examine the passages where Aristotle maintains that intellectual activity employs φαντάσματα (images) and argue that he requires awareness of the relevant images. This, together with Aristotle’s claims about the universality of understanding, gives us reason to reject the interpretation of Michael Wedin and Victor Caston, on which φαντάσματα serve as the material basis for thinking. I develop a new interpretation by unpacking the comparison Aristotle makes to the role of diagrams in doing geometry. In theoretical understanding of mathematical and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Noῦs and Nature in De Anima III.Sarah Broadie - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):163-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle's Cognitive Science: Belief, Affect and Rationality.Ian Mccready-Flora - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2):394-435.
    I offer a novel interpretation of Aristotle's psychology and notion of rationality, which draws the line between animal and specifically human cognition. Aristotle distinguishes belief (doxa), a form of rational cognition, from imagining (phantasia), which is shared with non-rational animals. We are, he says, “immediately affected” by beliefs, but respond to imagining “as if we were looking at a picture.” Aristotle's argument has been misunderstood; my interpretation explains and motivates it. Rationality includes a filter that interrupts the pathways between cognition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why the Intellect Cannot Have a Bodily Organ: De Anima 3.4.Caleb Cohoe - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (4):347-377.
    I reconstruct Aristotle’s reasons for thinking that the intellect cannot have a bodily organ. I present Aristotle’s account of the aboutness or intentionality of cognitive states, both perceptual and intellectual. On my interpretation, Aristotle’s account is based around the notion of cognitive powers taking on forms in a special preservative way. Based on this account, Aristotle argues that no physical structure could enable a bodily part or combination of bodily parts to produce or determine the full range of forms that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology.James G. Lennox - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (1):1-16.
    Historians of psychology often treat Aristotle’s De Anima as the first scientific treatment of their subject; and historians of biology do likewise with his zoological treatises. How are the investigations recorded in works such as the Parts of Animals and History of Animals connected to those in the De Anima? More specifically, given Aristotle’s views about man’s special and distinctive cognitive capacities, what does he think about man as an object of a distinctively zoological investigation? In the following pages, this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Unity of Intellect in Aristotle's De Anima.Lloyd Gerson - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (4):348-373.
    Desperately difficult texts inevitably elicit desperate hermeneutical measures. Aristotle's De Anima, book three, chapter five, is evidently one such text. At least since the time of Alexander of Aphrodisias, scholars have felt compelled to draw some remarkable conclusions regarding Aristotle's brief remarks in this passage regarding intellect. One such claim is that in chapter five, Aristotle introduces a second intellect, the so-called 'agent intellect', an intellect distinct from the 'passive intellect', the supposed focus of discussion up until this passage.1 This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Aristotle and the problem of intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only formulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls "phantasia." The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano's) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Content and cause in the aristotelian mind.Michael V. Wedin - 1993 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1):49-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Naturalizing Nous? Theophrastus on Nous, Nature, and Motion.Andrea Falcon & Robert Roreitner - 2024 - Phronesis 69 (4):468-499.
    There is prima facie evidence that Theophrastus naturalized nous to the extent that he spoke of it in naturalizing terms. But our evidence also suggests that Theophrastus accepted the reasons Aristotle had for excluding nous from the reach of natural philosophy. We show that, far from revealing an inconsistency on Theophrastus’ part, this apparent tension results from a consciously adopted strategy. Theophrastus is developing one aspect of Aristotle’s account of nous he found underdeveloped and feared might be misunderstood, namely the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the Mechanics of Thought.Michael V. Wedin - 1989 - Ancient Philosophy 9 (1):67-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Change, Agency and the Incomplete in Aristotle.Andreas Anagnostopoulos - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (2):170-209.
    Aristotle’s most fundamental distinction between changes and other activities is not that ofMetaphysicsΘ.6, between end-exclusive and end-inclusive activities, but one implicit inPhysics3.1’s definition of change, between the activity of something incomplete and the activity of something complete. Notably, only the latter distinction can account for Aristotle’s view, inPhysics3.3, that ‘agency’—effecting change in something, e.g. teaching—does not qualify strictly as a change. This distinction informsDe Anima2.5 and imparts unity to Aristotle’s extended treatment of change inPhysics3.1-3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle on Nature, Human Nature and Human Understanding.Mor Segev - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (2):177-209.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Rhizomata Jahrgang: 5 Heft: 2 Seiten: 177-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theophrastus and the Intellect as Mixture.Myrna Gabbe - 2008 - Elenchos 29 (1):61-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Phantasia and Thought.Victor Caston - 2008 - In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 322-34.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Phantasia Thought Notes Bibliography.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Victor Caston - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (3):199-227.
    In "De anima" 3.5, Aristotle argues for the existence of a second intellect, the so-called "Agent Intellect." The logical structure of his argument turns on a distinction between different types of soul, rather than different faculties within a given soul; and the attributes he assigns to the second species make it clear that his concern here -- as at the climax of his other great works, such as the "Metaphysics," the "Nicomachean" and the "Eudemian Ethics" -- is the difference between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Heart and Soul in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals II.Christof Rapp - 2022 - In Sabine Föllinger (ed.), Aristotle’s ›Generation of Animals‹: A Comprehensive Approach. De Gruyter. pp. 269-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Peripatetic Philosophy in Context: Knowledge, Time, and Soul From Theophrastus to Cratippus.Francesco Verde - 2022 - Berlin: De Gruyter.
    This book deals with some Peripatetic philosophers of the Hellenistic age who were direct and indirect pupils of Aristotle. The main focus of the book is Aristotle's school in the Hellenistic period, a subject not particularly explored by the scholars. Three main issues are addressed in the chapters of the book: the problem of knowledge, the question of time, and the doctrine of the soul. More specifically the topics addressed are: the problem of sense-perception and the method of multiple explanations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Embryology and Ackrill’s Problem.Nicola Carraro - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (3):274-304.
    Ackrill’s Problem is a tension between Aristotle’s alleged view that the matter of a living being is a body that is essentially ensouled, and his view that the matter of a substance preexists its generation. Most interpreters solve the tension by claiming that the subject of substantial generation is not the organic body of the living being, but its non-organic matter. I defend a different solution by showing that the embryological theory ofOn the Generation of Animalsimplies that the organic body (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Commentary on Kurt Pritzl: Aristotle on the conditions of thought.Victor Caston - 1998 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 14 (1):202-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alexandre d'Aphrodise, Commentaire Perdu À la "Physique" d'Aristote (Livres Iv-Viii): Les Scholies Byzantines. Édition, Traduction Et Commentaire.Marwan Rashed - 2011 - De Gruyter.
    Der heute verlorene Kommentar von Alexander aus Aphrodisias zur Physik des Aristoteles ist eines der wichtigsten Werke der Antike: beeinflusste er doch als Quelle sowohl die griechischen Kommentatoren des Aristoteles als auch - vermittelt durch die Araber - die Philosophie des Mittelalters. Die in dieser Ausgabe pr+sentierte Erstedition und Untersuchung der nahezu 700 byzantinischen Scholien, die erst j8ngst entdeckt wurden, erlauben eine genauere Rekonstruktion der physikalischen Lehren Alexanders und tragen zugleich zum besseren Verst+ndnis der Geschichte des Aristotelismus und der vorklassischen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Alexandre d'Aphrodise, Commentaire Perdu À la "Physique" d'Aristote : Les Scholies Byzantines. Édition, Traduction Et Commentaire.Marwan Rashed - 2011 - De Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Understanding Aristotle's Reproductive Hylomorphism.Devin Henry - 2006 - Apeiron 39 (3):257 - 287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Colloquium 5.Victor Caston - 2000 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):135-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle and other Platonists.Lloyd P. Gerson - 2005 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    "Aristotle versus Plato. For a long time that is the angle from which the tale has been told, in textbooks on the history of philosophy and to university students. Aristotle's philosophy, so the story goes, was au fond in opposition to Plato's. But it was not always thus."--from the Introduction In a wide-ranging book likely to cause controversy, Lloyd P. Gerson sets out the case for the "harmony" of Platonism and Aristotelianism, the standard view in late antiquity. He aims to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Aristotle on how to define a psychological state.Michael V. Wedin - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):11-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: A Moderate Interpretation of Aristotle’s De Memoria and De Anima on the Role of Images in Intellectual Activities.Caleb Cohoe - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (3):337-372.
    I offer a new interpretation of the passages where Aristotle maintains that intellectual activity employs φαντάσµατα (images). In theoretical understanding of mathematical and natural beings, we usually need to consciously employ appropriate φαντάσµατα in order to grasp explanatory connections. Aristotle does not, however, commit himself to thinking that images are required for exercising all theoretical understanding: understanding immaterial things, in particular, may not involve φαντάσµατα. Thus the connection that Aristotle makes between images and understanding does not rule out the possibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Perceptive Soul’s Impassivity in Late Ancient Reception of Aristotle’s De anima.Robert Roreitner - 2023 - Ancient Philosophy 43 (1):219-249.
    The article reconstructs a late ancient debate concerning a dilemma raised by Aristotle’s De anima: How can an impassive soul account for perceiving qua being affected by perceptual objects? It is argued that Alexander and Themistius developed radically different approaches which can be better understood within a larger context of the dialogue between Aristotelianism and Platonism. The debate is shown to be instructive in underlining difficulties inherent in Aristotle’s account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's Definition of Soul.William Charlton - 1980 - Phronesis 25 (2):170 - 186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle De Anima.Wm A. Hammond & R. D. Hicks - 1909 - Philosophical Review 18 (2):234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristoteles Lehre vom Ursprung des menschlichen Geistes.Franz Brentano - 1911 - Leipzig,: Velt & Comp. Edited by Mauro Antonelli, Thomas Binder & Ion Tănăsescu.
    F. Brentano. Franz Brentano ARISTOTELES LEHRE VOM URSPRUNG DES_ MENSOHLIOI-IEN GEISTES VON FRANZ BREN'I'ANO. Aristoteles Lehre vom Ursprung des menschlichen Geistes. Front Cover.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Soul, Seed and Palingenesis in the Hippocratic de Victu.Hynek Bartoš - 2009 - Apeiron 42 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Theophrastus on Perceiving.Victor Caston - 2019 - Rhizomata 7 (2):188-225.
    Many fragments from Theophrastus on perception are preserved by the late Neoplatonist, Priscian of Lydia. After preliminary source criticism concerning how to identify the fragments, I turn to Theophrastus’ discussion of perceiving and perceptual awareness. While he clearly rejects literalism, he also does not embrace “spiritualism”: he argues instead that we receive the defining proportions of perceptible qualities in the sense organ, though in different contraries than in the perceptible (thereby avoiding literalism). If Priscian’s report is faithful, Theophrastus also accepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Common to Body and Soul: Peripatetic Approaches After Aristotle.R. A. H. King - 2006 - In Common to Body and Soul: Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behaviour in Greco-Roman Antiquity. Walter de Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie.Victor Caston - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):177-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Über der Creationismus des Aristotels.Franz Brentano - 1882 - Stzungsberichte Der Kaiserlichen Akademie Der Wissenschaften 100:95-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nutritive and Sentient Soul in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals 2.5.Sophia M. Connell - 2020 - Phronesis 65 (3):324-354.
    This paper argues that focusing on Aristotle’s theory of generation as primarily ‘hylomorphic’ can lead to difficulties. This is especially evident when interpreting the association between the male and sentient soul at GA 2.5. If the focus is on the male’s contribution as form and the female’s as matter, then soul becomes divided into nutritive from female and sentient from male which makes little sense in Aristotle’s biological ontology. In contrast, by seeing Aristotle’s theory as ‘archēkinētic’, a process initiated by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Looking for the Formative Power in Aristotle’s Nutritive Soul.David Lefebvre - 2020 - In Giouli Korobili & Roberto Lo Presti (eds.), Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 101-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Artistotle's definition of soul.William Charlton - 1993 - In Michael Durrant (ed.), Aristotle's de Anima in Focus. New York: Routledge. pp. 170-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Soul and its Instrumental Body. A Reinterpretation of Aristotle's Philosophy of Living Nature.A. Bos - 2004 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2):386-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I.D. M. Balme & Richard Sorabji - 1972 - Philosophy 48 (186):404-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • La théorie aristotélicienne de l’intellect d’après Theophraste.Edmond Barbotin - 1953 - Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy 14:276-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Stages in the Development of Language about Aristotle's nous.Pamela Huby - 1991 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy:129-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations