Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The concept of truth in formalized languages.Alfred Tarski - 1956 - In Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Oxford,: Clarendon Press. pp. 152--278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   533 citations  
  • The Logical Syntax of Language.Rudolf Carnap - 1937 - London: Routledge. Edited by Amethe Smeaton.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   181 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    "This book is valuable as expounding in full a theory of meaning that has its roots in the work of Frege and has been of the widest influence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   683 citations  
  • On Logical Relativity.Achille C. Varzi - 2002 - Philosophical Issues 12 (1):197-219.
    One logic or many? I say—many. Or rather, I say there is one logic for each way of specifying the class of all possible circumstances, or models, i.e., all ways of interpreting a given language. But because there is no unique way of doing this, I say there is no unique logic except in a relative sense. Indeed, given any two competing logical theories T1 and T2 (in the same language) one could always consider their common core, T, and settle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Presidential Address: The Schematic Fallacy.Timothy Smiley - 1983 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83:1 - 17.
    Timothy Smiley; I*—The Presidential Address: The Schematic Fallacy, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 1–18, https.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • I*—The Presidential Address: The Schematic Fallacy.Timothy Smiley - 1983 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83 (1):1-18.
    Timothy Smiley; I*—The Presidential Address: The Schematic Fallacy, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 1–18, https.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Formal and material consequence.Stephen Read - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (3):247 - 265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • What is a logical constant?Christopher Peacocke - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (9):221-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Reassessing logical hylomorphism and the demarcation of logical constants.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):387 - 410.
    The paper investigates the propriety of applying the form versus matter distinction to arguments and to logic in general. Its main point is that many of the currently pervasive views on form and matter with respect to logic rest on several substantive and even contentious assumptions which are nevertheless uncritically accepted. Indeed, many of the issues raised by the application of this distinction to arguments seem to be related to a questionable combination of different presuppositions and expectations; this holds in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The idea of a logical constant.Timothy McCarthy - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (9):499-523.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Logical constants.John MacFarlane - 2008 - Mind.
    Logic is usually thought to concern itself only with features that sentences and arguments possess in virtue of their logical structures or forms. The logical form of a sentence or argument is determined by its syntactic or semantic structure and by the placement of certain expressions called “logical constants.”[1] Thus, for example, the sentences Every boy loves some girl. and Some boy loves every girl. are thought to differ in logical form, even though they share a common syntactic and semantic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Logical Constants.K. Warmbrõd - 1999 - Mind 108 (431):503 - 538.
    There is as yet no settled consensus as to what makes a term a logical constant or even as to which terms should be recognized as having this status. This essay sets out and defends a rationale for identifying logical constants. I argue for a two-tiered approach to logical theory. First, a secure, core logical theory recognizes only a minimal set of constants needed for deductively systematizing scientific theories. Second, there are extended logical theories whose objectives are to systematize various (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Logical constants across varying types.Johan van Benthem - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (3):315-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Logic, Logics, and Logicism.Solomon Feferman - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (1):31-54.
    The paper starts with an examination and critique of Tarski’s wellknown proposed explication of the notion of logical operation in the type structure over a given domain of individuals as one which is invariant with respect to arbitrary permutations of the domain. The class of such operations has been characterized by McGee as exactly those definable in the language L∞,∞. Also characterized similarly is a natural generalization of Tarski’s thesis, due to Sher, in terms of bijections between domains. My main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The concept of logical consequence.John Etchemendy - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Of course we all know now that mathematics has proved that logic doesn't really make sense, but Etchemendy (philosophy, Stanford Univ.) goes further and challenges the received view of the conceptual underpinnings of modern logic by arguing that Tarski's model-theoretic analysis of logical consequences is wrong. He may have found the soft underbelly of the dead horse. Annotation copyrighted by Book News, Inc., Portland, OR.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Logical Syntax and Semantics: Their Linguistic Relevance.Noam Chomsky - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1):72-72.
    The relation between linguistics and logic has been discussed in a, recent paper by Bar-Hillel} where it is argued that a disregard for workin logical syntax and semantics has caused linguists to limit themselves too narrowly in their inquiries, and to fall into several errors. In particular, Bar-Hillel asserts, they have attempted to derive relations of synonymy and so-called ‘rules of transfOI`1'Il8.tiOH,, such as the active—pussive relation, from distributional studies alone, and they have hesitated to rely on considerations of meaning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Logical Syntax of Language.Rudolph Carnap - 1936 - Philosophical Review 46 (5):549-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Logicality and Invariance.Denis Bonnay - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):29-68.
    What is a logical constant? The question is addressed in the tradition of Tarski's definition of logical operations as operations which are invariant under permutation. The paper introduces a general setting in which invariance criteria for logical operations can be compared and argues for invariance under potential isomorphism as the most natural characterization of logical operations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - MIT Press.
    The Bounds of Logic presents a new philosophical theory of the scope and nature of logic based on critical analysis of the principles underlying modern Tarskian logic and inspired by mathematical and linguistic development. Extracting central philosophical ideas from Tarski’s early work in semantics, Sher questions whether these are fully realized by the standard first-order system. The answer lays the foundation for a new, broader conception of logic. By generally characterizing logical terms, Sher establishes a fundamental result in semantics. Her (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English.Richard Montague - 1973 - In Patrick Suppes, Julius Moravcsik & Jaakko Hintikka (eds.), Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht. pp. 221--242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   357 citations  
  • Logical Consequence: Between Formal and Natural Language (Dissertation).Gil Sagi - 2013 - Dissertation, Hebrew University of Jerusalem
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Does It Mean to Say That Logic is Formal?John MacFarlane - 2000 - Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh
    Much philosophy of logic is shaped, explicitly or implicitly, by the thought that logic is distinctively formal and abstracts from material content. The distinction between formal and material does not appear to coincide with the more familiar contrasts between a priori and empirical, necessary and contingent, analytic and synthetic—indeed, it is often invoked to explain these. Nor, it turns out, can it be explained by appeal to schematic inference patterns, syntactic rules, or grammar. What does it mean, then, to say (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English.Richard Montague - 1974 - In Richmond H. Thomason (ed.), Formal Philosophy. Yale University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   402 citations  
  • The Concept of Logical Consequence.John Etchemendy - 1994 - Erkenntnis 41 (2):281-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations