Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Bloomsbury Companion to Kant

London: Bloomsbury Academic (2015)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Acting from duty: Inclination, reason and moral worth.Jens Timmermann - 2009 - In Kant's Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals: a critical guide. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Section I of Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals is meant to lead us from our everyday conception of morality to the supreme principle of all moral action, officially christened the ‘categorical imperative’ some twenty Academy pages further into the treatise. It is quite striking that in this first section Kant dispenses with the notorious technical language that pervades not just other parts of the Groundwork but also most of the remaining philosophical writings of the critical period. The mere (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant on Construction, Apriority, and the Moral Relevance of Universalization.Timothy Rosenkoetter - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (6):1143-1174.
    This paper introduces a referential reading of Kant’s practical project, according to which maxims are made morally permissible by their correspondence to objects, though not the ontic objects of Kant’s theoretical project but deontic objects (what ought to be). It illustrates this model by showing how the content of the Formula of Universal Law might be determined by what our capacity of practical reason can stand in a referential relation to, rather than by facts about what kind of beings we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Supplement.[author unknown] - 1992 - New Vico Studies 10:145-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Supplement.[author unknown] - 1989 - New Vico Studies 7:162-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Preamble.[author unknown] - 1999 - Augustinian Studies 30 (1):19-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Great Philosophers?[author unknown] - 2009 - The Philosopher 97 (1).
    The Great Philosophers, by Jeremy Stangroom and James Garvey, Arcturus 2005/ 2008 ISBN 9781848370180, pp160 UKP9.99 and Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books, by James Garvey, Continuum 2006, pp181 UKP 10.99100 Essential Thinkers, by Philip Stokes, Arcturus 2002/2006 ISBN 0572032064 pp218 UKP 8.99A Brief History of Philosophy from Socrates to Derrida, by Derek Johnston, Continuum 2006 pb ISBN 0826490204 pp206The Great Philosophers: the lives and ideas of History's greatest thinkers, by Stephen Law, Quercus UKP15 ISBN 1-84724-398-3 hb.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Einleitung.[author unknown] - 2019 - Zeitschrift Für Evangelische Ethik 63 (3):161-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conclusion.[author unknown] - 1926 - Archives de Philosophie 4 (3):112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Inferentialism and the Transcendental Deduction.David Landy - 2009 - Kantian Review 14 (1):1-30.
    One recent trend in Kant scholarship has been to read Kant as undertaking a project in philosophical semantics, as opposed to, say, epistemology, or transcendental metaphysics. This trend has evolved almost concurrently with a debate in contemporary philosophy of mind about the nature of concepts and their content. Inferentialism is the view that the content of our concepts is essentially inferentially articulated, that is, that the content of a concept consists entirely, or in essential part, in the role that that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Appendix.[author unknown] - 1901 - Bibliothèque du Congrès International de Philosophie 3:693-695.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Appendix.[author unknown] - 1994 - Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft Und Geistesgeschichte 68 (1):289-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Persons as Causes in Kant.Wolfgang Ertl - 2010 - In Stephen R. Palmquist (ed.), Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 217-230.
    Drawing on recent Aristotelian readings of Kant's notion of natural causality with an emphasis on substances as causes, I will try to explain how persons can make a difference in the world of appearances by virtue of their rationality. For Kant, the clue is that the peculiar mode of a substance's natural causality supervenes on in-itself features, among which is the mode or character of the person's rationality. Thus, a wedge can be driven between natural necessity and metaphysical necessity, opening (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Internal and External Reasons.Bernard Williams - 1979 - In Ross Harrison (ed.), Rational action: studies in philosophy and social science. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 101-113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   564 citations  
  • Kant.Robert Paul Wolff - 1967 - Garden City, N.Y.,: Anchor Books.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Awe or envy: Herder contra Kant on the sublime.Rachel Zuckert - 2003 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (3):217–232.
    I present and evaluate Johann Gottfried Herder's criticisms of Kant's account of the sublime and Herder's own theory of the sublime, as presented in his work, Kalligone. Herder's account and criticisms ought to be taken seriously, I argue, as (respectively) a non-reductive, naturalist aesthetics of the sublime, and as illuminating the metaphysical, moral, and political presuppositions underlying Kant's (and Burke's) accounts of the sublime.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Kant’s Political Anthropology.Günter Zöller - 2011 - Kant Yearbook 3 (1):131-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The unity of a theme: The subject of judgements of taste.Melissa Zinkin - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (3):469 – 488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Respect for the law and the use of dynamical terms in Kant's theory of moral motivation.Melissa Zinkin - 2006 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88 (1):31-53.
    Kant's discussion of the feeling of respect presents a puzzle regarding both the precise nature of this feeling and its role in his moral theory as an incentive that motivates us to follow the moral law. If it is a feeling that motivates us to follow the law, this would contradict Kant's view that moral obligation is based on reason alone. I argue that Kant has an account of respect as feeling that is nevertheless not separate from the use of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kant on Negative Magnitudes.Melissa Zinkin - 2012 - Kant Studien 103 (4):397-414.
    : Kant’s 1763 essay, Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy, is one of the least discussed of all his pre-critical writings. When it is referred to, it is usually just to note a few passages that anticipate Kant’s later, Critical philosophy. I argue that instead of understanding these early anticipations of the Critical philosophy as separable from Kant’s discussion of negative magnitudes, we should take their origin in Kant’s investigation of negative magnitudes to be of central (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Anthropology, Empirical Psychology, and Applied Logic.Job Zinkstok - 2011 - Kant Yearbook 3 (1):107-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable.Nick Zangwill - 1995 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (2):167 - 176.
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1995.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • ‘This inscrutable principle of an original organization’: epigenesis and ‘looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science.John H. Zammito - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):73-109.
    Kant’s philosophy of science takes on sharp contour in terms of his interaction with the practicing life scientists of his day, particularly Johann Blumenbach and the latter’s student, Christoph Girtanner, who in 1796 attempted to synthesize the ideas of Kant and Blumenbach. Indeed, Kant’s engagement with the life sciences played a far more substantial role in his transcendental philosophy than has been recognized hitherto. The theory of epigenesis, especially in light of Kant’s famous analogy in the first Critique, posed crucial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • From Gratification to Justice. The Tension between Anthropology and Pure Practical Reason in Kant’s Conception(s) of the Highest Good.Thomas Wyrwich - 2011 - Kant Yearbook 3 (1):91-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Activity of Sensibility in Kant’s Anthropology. A Developmental History of the Concept of the Formative Faculty.Matthias Wunsch - 2011 - Kant Yearbook 3 (1):67-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Sense and Sensibility in Kant's Practical Agent: Against the Intellectualism of Korsgaard and Sidgwick.Julian Wuerth - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):1-36.
    Drawing on a wide range of Kant's recorded thought beyond his Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, this essay presents an overview of Kant's account of practical agency as embodied practical agency and argues against the intellectualized interpretations of Kant's account of practical agency presented by Christine Korsgaard and Henry Sidgwick. In both Kant's empirical-psychological and metaphysical descriptions of practical agency, he presents a recognizably human practical agent that is broader and deeper than the faculty of reason alone. This agent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Aesthetics of Mimesis Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. [REVIEW]Sarah E. Worth - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (1):194-194.
    Steven Halliwell’s book has set a new standard in the scholarship on the philosophical aspects of mimesis. The book is clearly written, extensively researched, and, most importantly, it is a comprehensive analysis of the history and development of the complex, but often oversimplified, notion of mimesis. This is the kind of book scholars are lucky to come across in doing their own research, and a book of this level of achievement is something that we can all use as a model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant.Allen W. Wood - 2004 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Kant on Autonomy and the Value of Persons.Eric Entrican Wilson - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):241-262.
    This essay seeks to contribute to current debates about value in Kant's ethics. Its main objective is to dislodge the widely shared intuition that his view of autonomy requires constructivism or some other alternative to moral realism. I argue the following. Kant seems to think that the value of persons is due to their very nature, not to what anyone decides is the case (however rational or pure those decisions may be). He also seems to think that when we treat (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Between Ethics and Right: Kantian Politics and Democratic Purposes.Garrath Williams - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):479-486.
    Arthur Ripstein's book Force and Freedom insists that, ‘Freedom, understood as independence of another person's choice, is [all] that matters’. In this paper I suggest that this premise leads Ripstein to an instrumentalization of democracy that neglects a properly public and collective notion of freedom. The paper first criticizes Ripstein's key argument against any extension of public purposes beyond the upholding of persons’ ‘independence of others’ choice’. More constructively, the paper then suggests that a space of public freedom is opened (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Metaphysical foundations of morality in Kant.Victoria S. Wike - 1983 - Journal of Value Inquiry 17 (3):225-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dependent beauty as the appreciation of teleological style.Robert Wicks - 1997 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (4):387-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The metaphysics of disinterestedness: Shaftesbury and Kant.David A. White - 1973 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 32 (2):239-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Metaphysics of Disinterestedness: Shaftesbury and Kant.David A. White - 1969 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 28 (2):239-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant finds nothing ugly?Christian Wenzel - 1999 - British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (4):416-422.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Subjective Basis of Kant's Judgment of Taste.Brian Watkins - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (4):315-336.
    Abstract Kant claims that the basis of a judgment of taste is a merely subjective representation and that the only merely subjective representations are feelings of pleasure or displeasure. Commentators disagree over how to interpret this claim. Some take it to mean that judgments about the beauty of an object depend only on the state of the judging subject. Others argue instead that, for Kant, the pleasure we take in a beautiful object is best understood as a response to its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Antinomy of Teleological Judgment.Eric Watkins - 2009 - Kant Yearbook 1 (1):197-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Duty of Self-Knowledge.Owen Ware - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (3):671-698.
    Kant is well known for claiming that we can never really know our true moral disposition. He is less well known for claiming that the injunction "Know Yourself" is the basis of all self-regarding duties. Taken together, these two claims seem contradictory. My aim in this paper is to show how they can be reconciled. I first address the question of whether the duty of self-knowledge is logically coherent (§1). I then examine some of the practical problems surrounding the duty, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The truth of the beautiful in the critique of judgement.Marcus Verhaegh - 2001 - British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (4):371-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant on the Nominal Definition of Truth.Alberto Vanzo - 2010 - Kant Studien 101 (2):147-166.
    Kant claims that the nominal definition of truth is: “Truth is the agreement of cognition with its object”. In this paper, I analyse the relevant features of Kant's theory of definition in order to explain the meaning of that claim and its consequences for the vexed question of whether Kant endorses or rejects a correspondence theory of truth. I conclude that Kant's claim implies neither that he holds, nor that he rejects, a correspondence theory of truth. Kant's claim is not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • How biological is human history? Kant's use of biological concepts and its implications for history as moral anthropology.Liesbet Vanhaute - 2011 - Hegel Bulletin 32 (1-2):252-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beauty, Disinterested Pleasure, and Universal Communicability: Kant’s Response to Burke.Bart Vandenabeele - 2012 - Kant Studien 103 (2):207-233.
    : Although Kant holds that the universal communicability of aesthetic judgments logically follows from the disinterested character of the pleasure upon which they are based, Kant’s emphasis on the a priori validity of judgments of beauty can be viewed as a rebuttal of the kind of empiricist arguments that Burke offers to justify the social nature of the experience of beauty. I argue that the requirement of universal communicability is not a mere addition to the requirement of universal validity and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The system of transcendental idealism: Questions raised and left open in the kritik der urteilskraft.Burkhard Tuschling - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):109-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The System of Transcendental Idealism: Questions Raised and Left Open in the Kritik der Urteilskraft.Burkhard Tuschling - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1):109-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • From Shaftesbury To Kant: The Development Of The Concept Of Aesthetic Experience.Dabney Townsend - 1987 - Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (April-June):287-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Bolzano and Kant on the Nature of Logic.Clinton Tolley - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (4):307-327.
    Here I revisit Bolzano's criticisms of Kant on the nature of logic. I argue that while Bolzano is correct in taking Kant to conceive of the traditional logic as a science of the activity of thinking rather than the content of thought, he is wrong to charge Kant with a failure to identify and examine this content itself within logic as such. This neglects Kant's own insistence that traditional logic does not exhaust logic as such, since it must be supplemented (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kantian Meta-Aesthetics and the Neglected Alternative.J. J. Tinguely - 2013 - British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (2):211-235.
    In this article, firstly, I begin by articulating four logically different positions Kant has been argued to hold concerning the nature and meaning of ‘aesthetic judgement’ so that, secondly, I may endorse the alternative that has been almost entirely neglected: that is, aesthetic judgement should be understood to be both ‘internalist’ in that the pleasure of taste is a constitutive element of the judgement itself (rather than its external effect or prior referent) and ‘objective’ insofar as the pleasure of taste (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant und Euler.H. E. Timerding - 1919 - Kant Studien 23 (1-3):18-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Contradictions and the Categorical Imperative.Mark Timmons - 1984 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 66 (3):294-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant's problems with ugliness.Garrett Thomson - 1992 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (2):107-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant, McDowell and the Theory of Consciousness.Alan Thomas - 2002 - European Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):283-305.
    This paper examines some of the central arguments of John McDowell's Mind and World, particularly his treatment of the Kantian themes of the spontaneity of thought and of the nature of self-consciousness. It is argued that in so far as McDowell departs from Kant, his position becomes less plausible in three respects. First, the space of reason is identified with the space of responsible and critical freedom in a way that runs together issues about synthesis below the level of concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations