Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Common ground.Robert Stalnaker - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):701-721.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   483 citations  
  • It's immaterial (a reply to Sinnott-armstrong).William G. Lycan - 1999 - Philosophical Papers 28 (2):133-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Do Conditionals Have Truth Conditions?Dorothy Edgington - 1986 - Instituto de Investigaciones Filosófica, Unam.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Relevant Logic: A Philosophical Examination of Inference.Stephen Read - 1988 - New York, NY, USA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Ifs, Ands, and Buts: An Incremental Truthmaker Semantics for Indicative Conditionals.Stephen Yablo - 2016 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (1):175-213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Keeping Track of Nozick.Crispin Wright - 1983 - Analysis 43 (3):134 - 140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Conditionals, Modals, and Hypothetical Syllogism.Lee Walters - 2014 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):90-97.
    Moti Mizrahi (2013) presents some novel counterexamples to Hypothetical Syllogism (HS) for indicative conditionals. I show that they are not compelling as they neglect the complicated ways in which conditionals and modals interact. I then briefly outline why HS should nevertheless be rejected.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Against Hypothetical Syllogism.Lee Walters - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (5):979-997.
    The debate over Hypothetical Syllogism is locked in stalemate. Although putative natural language counterexamples to Hypothetical Syllogism abound, many philosophers defend Hypothetical Syllogism, arguing that the alleged counterexamples involve an illicit shift in context. The proper lesson to draw from the putative counterexamples, they argue, is that natural language conditionals are context-sensitive conditionals which obey Hypothetical Syllogism. In order to make progress on the issue, I consider and improve upon Morreau’s proof of the invalidity of Hypothetical Syllogism. The improved proof (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Subjunctive conditionals: Two parameters vs. three.Pavel Tichý - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 45 (2):147 - 179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • If-iculties.Charles L. Stevenson - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (1):27-49.
    The discrepancy between English if's and the horseshoe is far from being negligible. That is not a reason for distrusting the horseshoe, which is useful so long as it is taken to mean just what it is defined to mean; and it is not a reason for distrusting our English if's, which in spite of their ambiguities are indispensable to our daily discourse. But it is a reason for distrusting the current logical pedagogy that leads students to take the two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Indicative conditionals.Robert Stalnaker - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (3):269-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Utilitarianisms: Simple and general.J. Howard Sobel - 1970 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 13 (1-4):394 – 449.
    If we overlook no consequences when we assess the act, and no relevant features when we generalize, can it matter whether we ask 'What would happen if everyone did the same?' instead of 'What would happen if this act were performed?'? David Lyons has argued that it cannot. Two examples are here articulated to show that it can. The first turns on the way consequences are identified and assessed and in particular on the treatment accorded 'threshold consequences'. The second example (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The switches paradox: Which switch?Tom Settle - 1973 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 33 (3):421-428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Old Adams Buried.Ian Rumfitt - 2013 - Analytic Philosophy 54 (2):157-188.
    I present some counterexamples to Adams's Thesis and explain how they undermine arguments that indicative conditionals cannot be truth-evaluable propositions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Relevant logic: a philosophical examination of inference.Stephen Read - 1988 - Oxford: Blackwell.
    The logician's central concern is with the validity of argument. A logical theory ought, therefore, to provide a general criterion of validity. This book sets out to find such a criterion, and to describe the philosophical basis and the formal theory of a logic in which the premises of a valid argument are relevant to its conclusion. The notion of relevance required for this theory is obtained by an analysis of the grounds for asserting a formula in a proof.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Conditionals Are Not Truth-Functional: An Argument from Peirce.Stephen Read - 1992 - Analysis 52 (1):5 - 12.
    Peirce's example puts another nail in the coffin of the truth-functionality thesis. Conditionals are not truth-functional.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Note on the switches paradox.R. Z. Parks - 1972 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 32 (3):408-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why Hypothetical Syllogism is Invalid for Indicative Conditionals.Moti Mizrahi - 2013 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):40-43.
    In this article, I present a schema for generating counterexamples to the argument form known as Hypothetical Syllogism with indicative conditionals. If my schema for generating counterexamples to HS works as I think it does, then HS is invalid for indicative conditionals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • How to Believe a Conditional.D. H. Mellor - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (5):233-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The problem of true-true counterfactuals.Aidan McGlynn - 2012 - Analysis 72 (2):276-285.
    Early commentators on David Lewis's account of counterfactuals noted that certain examples suggest that some counterfactuals with true antecedents and true consequents are false. Lewis's account has the consequence that all such counterfactuals are true, leaving us to choose between explaining away our intuitions about the examples in question or offering an alternative to Lewis's account. Here I argue that a simple modification of the familiar Lewisian truth conditions yields the intuitively correct verdicts about these examples, and so we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Redundant causation.Michael McDermott - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (4):523-544.
    I propose an amendment of Lewis's counterfactual analysis of causation, designed to overcome some difficulties concerning redundant causation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Why we need a relevant theory of conditionals.Edwin D. Mares - 1994 - Topoi 13 (1):31-36.
    This paper presents ConR (Conditional R), a logic of conditionals based on Anderson and Belnap''s system R. A Routley-Meyer-style semantics for ConR is given for the system (the completeness of ConR over this semantics is proved in E. Mares and A. Fuhrmann, A Relevant Theory of Conditionals (unpublished MS)). Moreover, it is argued that adopting a relevant theory of conditionals will improve certain theories that utilize conditionals, i.e. Lewis'' theory of causation, Lewis'' dyadic deontic logic, and Chellas'' dyadic deontic logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • MPP, Rip.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Philosophical Perspectives 7:411-428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Interesting theorems in symbolic logic.C. I. Lewis - 1913 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 10 (9):239-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Elusive knowledge.David K. Lewis - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):549 – 567.
    David Lewis (1941-2001) was Class of 1943 University Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. His contributions spanned philosophical logic, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, metaphysics, and epistemology. In On the Plurality of Worlds, he defended his challenging metaphysical position, "modal realism." He was also the author of the books Convention, Counterfactuals, Parts of Classes, and several volumes of collected papers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1014 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David K. Lewis - 1973 - Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
    Counterfactuals is David Lewis' forceful presentation of and sustained argument for a particular view about propositions which express contrary to fact conditionals, including his famous defense of realism about possible worlds and his theory of laws of nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1278 citations  
  • The meaning of `if' in conditional propositions.Geoffrey Hunter - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (172):279-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On the switches paradox.Daniel Gogol - 1972 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 32 (3):410-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Peirce's Challenge to Material Implication as a Model of 'If'.Brendan S. Gillon - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):280 - 282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Counterfactual scorekeeping.Anthony S. Gillies - 2007 - Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (3):329 - 360.
    Counterfactuals are typically thought--given the force of Sobel sequences--to be variably strict conditionals. I go the other way. Sobel sequences and (what I call) Hegel sequences push us to a strict conditional analysis of counterfactuals: counterfactuals amount to some necessity modal scoped over a plain material conditional, just which modal being a function of context. To make this worth saying I need to say just how counterfactuals and context interact. No easy feat, but I have something to say on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Conditionals in context.Christopher Gauker - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (3):293 - 321.
    This paper is obsolete. It is superseded by the book, Conditionals in Context, MIT Press, 2005.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Conditionals in Context.Christopher Gauker - 2005 - MIT Press.
    "If you turn left at the next corner, you will see a blue house at the end of the street." That sentence -- a conditional -- might be true even though it is possible that you will not see a blue house at the end of the street when you turn left at the next corner. A moving van may block your view; the house may have been painted pink; a crow might swoop down and peck out your eyes. Still, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • David Lewis on indicative and counterfactual conditionals.R. J. Fogelin - 1998 - Analysis 58 (4):286-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On conditionals.Dorothy Edgington - 1995 - Mind 104 (414):235-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   449 citations  
  • Solving the skeptical problem.Keith DeRose - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):1-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   628 citations  
  • Comparative world similarity and what is held fixed in counterfactuals.C. B. Cross - 2011 - Analysis 71 (1):91-96.
    Berit Brogaard and Joe Salerno (Counterfactuals and Context, ANALYSIS 68 (2008): 39-46) argue that the standard Stalnaker-Lewis counterexamples to hypothetical syllogism, strengthening the antecedent, and contraposition trade on a failure to hold fixed the context in which truth values are determined for the premises and conclusion in each counterexample. I argue that no contextual fallacy is committed in the standard counterexamples, and I offer a different view of what it is for a fact to be held fixed by a counterfactual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The switches "paradox" and the limits of propositional logic.John Corcoran & Susan B. Wood - 1973 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 34 (1):102-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The propositional logic of ordinary discourse.William S. Cooper - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):295 – 320.
    The logical properties of the 'if-then' connective of ordinary English differ markedly from the logical properties of the material conditional of classical, two-valued logic. This becomes apparent upon examination of arguments in conversational English which involve (noncounterfactual) usages of if-then'. A nonclassical system of propositional logic is presented, whose conditional connective has logical properties approximating those of 'if-then'. This proposed system reduces, in a sense, to the classical logic. Moreover, because it is equivalent to a certain nonstandard three-valued logic, its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Knowledge, context, and social standards.Stewart Cohen - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):3 - 26.
    This paper defends the view that standards, which are typically social in nature, play a role in determining whether a subject has knowledge. While the argument focuses on standards that pertain to reasoning, I also consider whether there are similar standards for memory and perception.Ultimately, I argue that the standards are context sensitive and, as such, we must view attributions of knowledge as indexical. I exploit similarities between this view and a version of the relevant alternatives reply to skepticism in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Ifs and Hooks: A Rejoinder.Michael Clark - 1974 - Analysis 34 (January):77-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why is conjunctive simplification invalid?Bruce E. R. Thompson - 1991 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32 (2):248-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Counterfactuals and context.Berit Brogaard & Joe Salerno - 2008 - Analysis 68 (1):39–46.
    It is widely agreed that contraposition, strengthening the antecedent and hypothetical syllogism fail for subjunctive conditionals. The following putative counter-examples are frequently cited, respectively.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On some claims aboutif-then.Martin D. S. Braine - 1979 - Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (1):35 - 47.
    The paper has sought to show two things. One is that the apparent variety of Stalnaker and Lewis's counterexamples is misleading. Several of their examples are quite unsatisfactory because they depend on unguarded language behavior. There is in fact only one type of counterexample that is worth serious discussion, and that has the form of Barense's.For Barense's example, I try to show that it fails as a counterexample to transitivity because one of the premisses is false within the context of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The switches paradox.Robert L. Armstrong - 1970 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 30 (3):421-427.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Classical logic, conditionals and “nonmonotonic” reasoning.Nicholas Allott & Hiroyuki Uchida - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (1):85-85.
    Reasoning with conditionals is often thought to be non-monotonic, but there is no incompatibility with classical logic, and no need to formalise inference itself as probabilistic. When the addition of a new premise leads to abandonment of a previously compelling conclusion reached by modus ponens, for example, this is generally because it is hard to think of a model in which the conditional and the new premise are true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Logic of Conditionals.Ernest Adams, Ernest W. Adams, Jaakko Hintikka & Patrick Suppes - 1965 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (3):609-611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   267 citations  
  • Epistemic Logic in the Later Middle Ages.Ivan Boh - 1993 - London and New York: Routledge.
    _Epistemic Logic_ studies statements containing verbs such as 'know' and 'wish'. It is one of the most exciting areas in medieval philosophy. Neglected almost entirely after the end of the Middle Ages, it has been rediscovered by philosophers of the present century. This is the first comprehensive study of the subject. Ivan Boh explores the rules for entailment between epistemic statements, the search for the conditions of knowing contingent propositions, the problems of substitutivity in intentional contexts, the relationship between epistemic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Epistemic Logic in the Later Middle Ages.Ivan Boh - 1993 - London and New York: Routledge.
    _Epistemic Logic_ studies statements containing verbs such as 'know' and 'wish'. It is one of the most exciting areas in medieval philosophy. Neglected almost entirely after the end of the Middle Ages, it has been rediscovered by philosophers of the present century. This is the first comprehensive study of the subject. Ivan Boh explores the rules for entailment between epistemic statements, the search for the conditions of knowing contingent propositions, the problems of substitutivity in intentional contexts, the relationship between epistemic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and Epistemology of Demonstratives and other Indexicals.David Kaplan - 1989 - In Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes From Kaplan. Oxford University Press. pp. 481-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1668 citations  
  • Epistemic logic in the later Middle Ages.Ivan Boh - 1993 - New York: Routledge.
    Epistemic logic is one of the most exciting areas in medieval philosophy. Neglected almost entirely after the end of the Middle Ages, it has been rediscovered by philosophers of the twentieth century. Epistemic Logic in the Later Middle Ages provides the first comprehensive study of the subject. Ivan Boh explores the contrast between epistemic and alethic conceptions of consequence, the general epistemic rules of consequence, the search for conditions of knowing contingent propositions, the problems of substitutivity in intentional contexts, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations