Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Why Constitution is Not Identity.Lynne Rudder Baker - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (12):599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1928 citations  
  • Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I.Mark Okrent & Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (2):290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • Phenomenology of Perception.Aron Gurwitsch, M. Merleau-Ponty & Colin Smith - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (3):417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1362 citations  
  • (3 other versions)The paradox of subjectivity: The self in the transcendental tradition.David Carr - 1999 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):454-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • World as Horizon.Donn Welton - 2003 - In The New Husserl: A Critical Reader. Indiana University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Validity of Transcendental Arguments.Charles Taylor - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79:151 - 165.
    Charles Taylor; X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1 June 1979, Pages 151–166, https://do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • (1 other version)Internalism Defended.Richard Feldman & Earl Conee - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (1):1 - 18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • On the motives which led Husserl to transcendental idealism.Roman Ingarden - 1975 - Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
    INTRODUCTION I have often asked myself why Husserl, really, headed in the direction of transcendental idealism from the time of his ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Body in Husserl and Merleau-Ponty.Taylor Carman - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (2):205-226.
    The terminological boxes into which we press the history of philosophy often obscure deep and important differences among major figures supposedly belonging to a single school of thought. One such disparity within the phenomenological movement, often overlooked but by no means invisible, separates Merleau-Pontys Phenomenology of Perception from the Husserlian program that initially inspired it. For Merleau-Pontys phenomenology amounts to a radical, if discreet, departure not only from Husserls theory of intentionality generally, but more specifically from his account of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Kant's first analogy and the refutation of idealism.Mark Sacks - 2006 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1):113–130.
    In what follows I will address Kant’s concerns in the First Analogy and in the Refutation of Idealism. Because the two discussions have a similar trajectory, it is of interest to identify some of the differences between them. As we will see, the manifest differences are indicative of more significant underlying differences, regarding two ways of construing transcendental proofs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Husserl's notion of noema.Dagfinn Føllesdal - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (20):680-687.
    Darstellung des Noema in 12 Thesen.\nverwendete Textstellen: Ideen 1: S. 203, 22-23; S. 204, 20-21; S. 357, 19-20: Handlungen sind zielgerichtet. Dabei bedarf eines keines physischen Objekts. Husserl setzt and diese Stelle das Noema. Somit wird auch zielgerichtetes Handeln aufgrund einer Halluzination m{ö}glich, Zielgerichtet zu sein bedeutet ein Noema zu haben.\n1. Follesdal´sche These: Noema ist eine intensionale Entit{ä}t, eine Generalisierung des Begriffs Sinn/Bedeutung.\n2. These: Das Noema hat zwei Bestandteile, a) der noematische Sinn, der allen thetischen Handlungen (erinnern, sich vorstellen usw.) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Individualism and self-knowledge.Tyler Burge - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (November):649-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   367 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Individualism and the mental.Tyler Burge - 1979 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1):73-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1261 citations  
  • Husserl.David Bell - 1991 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 53 (4):718-720.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1749 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Philosophical Explanations. [REVIEW]Robert Nozick - 1981 - Philosophy 58 (223):118-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   858 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Philosophical Explanations.Robert Nozick - 1981 - Mind 93 (371):450-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   864 citations  
  • The Bounds of Sense.P. F. Strawson - 1966 - Philosophy 42 (162):379-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   406 citations  
  • Intentional Analysis and the Noema.Robert Sokolowski - 1984 - Dialectica 38 (2, 3):113-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl und Heidegger.Ernst Tugendhat - 1967 - Berlin,: De Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Internalism, externalism, and transcendental idealism.Dan Zahavi - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):355-374.
    The analyses of the mind–world relation offered by transcendental idealists such as Husserl have often been dismissed with the argument that they remain committed to an outdated form of internalism. The first move in this paper will be to argue that there is a tight link between Husserl’s transcendental idealism and what has been called phenomenological externalism, and that Husserl’s endorsement of the former commits him to a version of the latter. Secondly, it will be shown that key elements in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Husserl's noema and the internalism‐externalism debate.Dan Zahavi - 2004 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):42-66.
    In a number of papers, Hubert Dreyfus and Ronald McIntyre have claimed that Husserl is an internalist. In this paper, it is argued that their interpretation is based on two questionable assumptions: (1) that Husserl's noema should be interpreted along Fregean lines, and (2) that Husserl's transcendental methodology commits him to some form of methodological solipsism. Both of these assumptions are criticized on the basis of the most recent Husserl-research. It is shown that Husserl's concept of noema can be interpreted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Phenomenological immanence, normativity, and semantic externalism.Steven Crowell - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):335 - 354.
    This paper argues that transcendental phenomenology (here represented by Edmund Husserl) can accommodate the main thesis of semantic externalism, namely, that intentional content is not simply a matter of what is ‘in the head,’ but depends on how the world is. I first introduce the semantic problem as an issue of how linguistic tokens or mental states can have ‘content’—that is, how they can set up conditions of satisfaction or be responsive to norms such that they can succeed or fail (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Davidson’s Transcendental Externalism.Jason Bridges - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):290-315.
    One of the chief aims of Donald Davidson's later work was to show that participation in a certain causal nexus involving two creatures and a shared environment–Davidson calls this nexus “triangulation”–is a metaphysically necessary condition for the acquisition of thought. This doctrine, I suggest, is aptly regarded as a form of what I call transcendental externalism. I extract two arguments for the transcendental-externalist doctrine from Davidson's writings, and argue that neither succeeds. A central interpretive claim is that the arguments are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology.E. Husserl - 1960 - Philosophical Books 2 (2):4-5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   456 citations  
  • (3 other versions)The paradox of subjectivity: The self in the transcendental tradition.David Carr - 1999 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):454-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Davidson's Transcendental Externalism.Jason Bridges - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):290-315.
    One of the chief aims of Donald Davidson's later work was to show that participation in a certain causal nexus involving two creatures and a shared environment–Davidson calls this nexus “triangulation”–is a metaphysically necessary condition for the acquisition of thought. This doctrine, I suggest, is aptly regarded as a form of what I call transcendental externalism. I extract two arguments for the transcendental‐externalist doctrine from Davidson's writings, and argue that neither succeeds. A central interpretive claim is that the arguments are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Sartre's "Being and nothingness".S. Gardner - unknown
    Sebastian Gardner competently tackles one of Sartre's more complex and challenging works in this new addition to the Reader's Guides series.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Is there a phenomenological research program?Steven Crowell - 2002 - Synthese 131 (3):419-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Instantiation, identity and constitution.E. J. Lowe - 1983 - Philosophical Studies 44 (1):45 - 59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments.Charles Taylor - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1):151-166.
    Charles Taylor; X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1 June 1979, Pages 151–166, https://do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Sartre's Ontology.John Yolton & Albert Shalom - 1967 - Dialogue 6 (3):383-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Between Internalism and Externalism: Husserl’s Account of Intentionality.Lilian Alweiss - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (1):53-78.
    There is a strong consensus among analytic philosophers that Husserl is an internalist and that his internalism must be understood in conjunction with his methodological solipsism. This paper focuses on Husserl's early work the, Logical Investigations , and explores whether such a reading is justified. It shows that Husserl is not a methodological solipsist: He neither believes that meaning can be reduced to the individual, nor does he assign an explanatory role for meaning to the subject. Explanatory priority is assigned (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)On the Motives which Led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism. [REVIEW]Robert Sokolowski - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (3):176-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The metaphysic of en-soi and pour-soi.John W. Yolton - 1951 - Journal of Philosophy 48 (18):548-556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Is There A Phenomenological Research Program?Crowell Steven - 2002 - Synthese 131 (3):419-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Roman Ingarden, On the Motives which Led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism. [REVIEW]Robert Sokolowski - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (3):176-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Scepticism: Epistemic and Ontological.Anthony Rudd - 2000 - Metaphilosophy 31 (3):251-261.
    It is widely thought that sceptical arguments, if correct, would show that everyday empirical knowledge‐claims are false. Against this, I argue that the very generality of traditional sceptical arguments means that there is no direct incompatibility between everyday empirical claims and sceptical scenarios. Scepticism calls into doubt, not ordinary empirical beliefs, but philosophical attempts to give a deep ontological explanation of such beliefs. G. E. Moore's attempt to refute scepticism (and idealism) was unsuccessful, because it failed to recognise that philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (3 other versions)The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition.David Carr - 1999 - Human Studies 25 (1):117-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations