Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Some features of Hume's conception of space.Marina Frasca Spada - 1990 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 21 (3):371-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues.Roger Woolhouse & George Berkeley - 1957 - In George Berkeley & Colin M. Turbayne (eds.), A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. New York,: Liberal Arts Press.
    Berkeley's idealism started a revolution in philosophy. As one of the great empiricist thinkers he not only influenced British philosophers from Hume to Russell and the logical positivists in the twentieth century, he also set the scene for the continental idealism of Hegel and even the philosophy of Marx. -/- There has never been such a radical critique of common sense and perception as that given in Berkeley's Principles of Human Knowledge (1710). His views were met with disfavour, and his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Psychologistic Foundations of Hume's Critique of Mathematical Philosophy.Wayne Waxman - 1996 - Hume Studies 22 (1):123-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hume on Space and Geometry.Rosemary Newman - 1981 - Hume Studies 7 (1):1-31.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:HUME ON SPACE AND GEOMETRY Hume's discussion of our ideas of space, time and mathematics in Book One of the Treatise is referred to by one recent commentator as 'the least admired part' of this work, while another finds it to be 'one of the least satis2 factory Parts'. Hume himself, it would appear, was not far from endorsing such opinions. The omission of any detailed comment on these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hume on space (and time).Ben Lazare Mijuskovic - 1977 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 15 (4):387.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume on Space (and Time) BEN MIJUSKOVIC HUME'S LABYRINTHINE ANALYSES of our ideas of space and time, textually occuring so early in the Treatise, 1clearly testify to his conviction of their central role in the physical sciences, then making such fantastic progress. Furthermore, quite early in the Treatise, Hume indicates his ambition to effect a revolution in the mental sciences comparable to the one Newton had achieved in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hume on infinite divisibility and sensible extensionless indivisibles.Dale Jacquette - 1996 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (1):61-78.
    This essay examines David Hume's principal criticism of the idea of the infinite divisibility of extension in the ink-spot experiment of _Treatise<D>, Book I, Part II, and his arguments for his positive theory of finitely divisible space as composed of finitely many sensible extensionless indivisibles or _minima sensibilia<D>. The essay considers Hume's strict finitist metaphysics of space in the context of his reactions to a trilemma about the impossibility of the divisibility of extension on any theory posed by Pierre Bayle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Infinite Divisibility and Actual Parts in Hume’s Treatise.Thomas Holden - 2002 - Hume Studies 28 (1):3-25.
    According to a standard interpretation of Hume’s argument against infinite divisibility, Hume is raising a purely formal problem for mathematical constructions of infinite divisibility, divorced from all thought of the stuffing or filling of actual physical continua. I resist this. Hume’s argument must be understood in the context of a popular early modern account of the metaphysical status of the parts of physical quantities. This interpretation disarms the standard mathematical objections to Hume’s reasoning; I also defend it on textual and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Achievements and fallacies in Hume's account of infinite divisibility.James Franklin - 1994 - Hume Studies 20 (1):85-101.
    Throughout history, almost all mathematicians, physicists and philosophers have been of the opinion that space and time are infinitely divisible. That is, it is usually believed that space and time do not consist of atoms, but that any piece of space and time of non-zero size, however small, can itself be divided into still smaller parts. This assumption is included in geometry, as in Euclid, and also in the Euclidean and non- Euclidean geometries used in modern physics. Of the few (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Hume on Manners of Disposition and the Ideas of Space and Time.Lorne Falkenstein - 1997 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (2):179-201.
    Scholars have almost universally agreed that Hume's account of space and time as manners of disposition of impressions is inconsistent with one of the most fundamental tenets of his empiricism: the thesis that all ideas are derived from simple impressions. This paper challenges that view and argues that Hume's position on the origin of our ideas of space and time is a profound, original, virtually unique, and even courageous approach to the problem of original space and time cognition, and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Is Mathematics for Hume Synthetic a Priori?Dorothy P. Coleman - 1979 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 10 (2):113-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hume's Doctrine of Space.C. D. Broad - 1961 - Proceedings of the British Academy 47:161-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hume on Infinite Divisibility.Donald L. M. Baxter - 1988 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 5 (2):133-140.
    Hume seems to argue unconvincingly against the infinite divisibility of finite regions of space. I show that his conclusion is entailed by respectable metaphysical principles which he held. One set of principles entails that there are partless (unextended) things. Another set entails that these cannot be ordered so that an infinite number of them compose a finite interval.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations