Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Thinking and Doing, The Philosophical Foundations of Institutions.[author unknown] - 1977 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 39 (2):351-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Instrumental reasons.Niko Kolodny - 2018 - In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    Often our reason for doing something is an "instrumental reason": that doing that is a means to doing something else that we have reason to do. What principles govern this "instrumental transmission" of reasons from ends to means? Negatively, I argue against principles often invoked in the literature, which focus on necessary or sufficient means. Positively, I propose a principle, "General Transmission," which answers to two intuitive desiderata: that reason transmits to means that are "probabilizing" and "nonsuperfluous" with respect to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Imperatives, Logic Of.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell. pp. 2575-2585.
    Suppose that a sign at the entrance of a hotel reads: “Don’t enter these premises unless you are accompanied by a registered guest”. You see someone who is about to enter, and you tell her: “Don’t enter these premises if you are an unaccompanied registered guest”. She asks why, and you reply: “It follows from what the sign says”. It seems that you made a valid inference from an imperative premise to an imperative conclusion. But it also seems that imperatives (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A reply to my critics.George Edward Moore - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • Logic and the basis of ethics.Arthur Norman Prior - 1949 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
    This book discusses and aims to clarify the issue of describing conduct and character as ‘good’ or ‘bad’, or as ‘right’ or ‘wrong’. The book states that one of the main factors that have made this issue obscure is the illusion of some anti-naturalists that purely logical considerations can settle it. It clearly defines the limitations of the discussions: it is not concerned with the ‘other things’ people use to define conduct and character. The book attempts to consider the issue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Language of Morals.Richard Mervyn Hare - 1952 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Hare has written a clear, brief, and readable introduction to ethics which looks at all the fundamental problems of the subject.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   466 citations  
  • The language of morals.Richard Mervyn Hare - 1952 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
    Part I The Imperative Mood 'Virtue, then, is a disposition governing our choices '. ARISTOTLE, Eth. Nic. 36 Prescriptive Language. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   399 citations  
  • The logic of commands.Nicholas Rescher - 1966 - New York,: Dover Publications.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Propositional structure and illocutionary force: a study of the contribution of sentence meaning to speech acts.Jerrold J. Katz - 1977 - Hassocks [Eng.]: Harvester.
    Katz offers such a grammatical account, in which makes it possible for the first time to explain the illocutionary potential of sentences within grammar.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Consistency and Realism.Bernard A. O. Williams - 1966 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 40 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Poincarés Rule.Ota Weinberger - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ponicarés rule (oder: Ein bisschen hermeneutik, Herr Morscher!).Ota Weinberger - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):356-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • New foundations for imperative logic I: Logical connectives, consistency, and quantifiers.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2008 - Noûs 42 (4):529-572.
    Imperatives cannot be true or false, so they are shunned by logicians. And yet imperatives can be combined by logical connectives: "kiss me and hug me" is the conjunction of "kiss me" with "hug me". This example may suggest that declarative and imperative logic are isomorphic: just as the conjunction of two declaratives is true exactly if both conjuncts are true, the conjunction of two imperatives is satisfied exactly if both conjuncts are satisfied—what more is there to say? Much more, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • New Foundations for Imperative Logic: Pure Imperative Inference.P. B. M. Vranas - 2011 - Mind 120 (478):369-446.
    Imperatives cannot be true, but they can be obeyed or binding: `Surrender!' is obeyed if you surrender and is binding if you have a reason to surrender. A pure declarative argument — whose premisses and conclusion are declaratives — is valid exactly if, necessarily, its conclusion is true if the conjunction of its premisses is true; similarly, I suggest, a pure imperative argument — whose premisses and conclusion are imperatives — is obedience-valid (alternatively: bindingness-valid) exactly if, necessarily, its conclusion is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • In Defense of Imperative Inference.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (1):59 - 71.
    "Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight" is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an imperative. Several philosophers, however (Williams 1963; Wedeking 1970; Harrison 1991; Hansen 2008), have denied that imperative inferences exist, arguing that (1) no such inferences occur in everyday life, (2) imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, "since surrender" or "it follows that surrender or fight", and (3) distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • In Defense of Imperative Inference.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 55:85-92.
    “Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight” is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an imperative. Several philosophers, however, have denied that imperative inferences exist, arguing that no such inferences occur in everyday life, imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, “since surrender” or “it follows that surrender or fight”, and distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions, so issuing distinct imperatives amounts to changing one’s mind and thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • I Ought, Therefore I Can.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 136 (2):167-216.
    I defend the following version of the ought-implies-can principle: (OIC) by virtue of conceptual necessity, an agent at a given time has an (objective, pro tanto) obligation to do only what the agent at that time has the ability and opportunity to do. In short, obligations correspond to ability plus opportunity. My argument has three premises: (1) obligations correspond to reasons for action; (2) reasons for action correspond to potential actions; (3) potential actions correspond to ability plus opportunity. In the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Do Cry Over Spilt Milk.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2005 - The Monist 88 (3):370-387.
    There is widespread agreement, even among those who accept the possibility of backward causation, that it is impossible to change the past. I argue that this agreement corresponds to a relatively uninteresting understanding of what changing the past amounts to. In one sense it is indeed impossible to change the past: in no possible world is an action performed which makes the past in that world different from the past in that world. In another sense, however, it may be possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Deontic logic without deontic operators.Hermann Vetter - 1971 - Theory and Decision 2 (1):67-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Imperatives, logic, and moral obligation.Robert G. Turnbull - 1960 - Philosophy of Science 27 (4):374-390.
    It is claimed that 'Do x!' means 'Then you will do x'. Answering a "Why?" question concerning the former may take either of two forms, viz., 'Because --' or 'If you wish to --'. The second answer completes the truncated hypothetical. "Ought" sentences are treated as a species of imperatives involving universality in the "if" clause ('If anyone wished to --'). Moral "ought" sentences involve a double universality, viz., the one mentioned above and universality connecting the action with social harmony (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Intentions, beliefs, and imperative logic.R. F. Stalley - 1972 - Mind 81 (321):18-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Imperatives and Referential Opacity.Ernest Sosa - 1966 - Analysis 27 (2):49 - 52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ethics, persuasion, and truth.John Jamieson Carswell Smart - 1984 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    I INTRODUCTION FIRST ORDER QUESTIONS AND SECOND ORDER QUESTIONS In this book I wish to discuss certain questions that are about ethics rather than in ethics ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Imperatives and Logic.Alf Ross - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):48-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Imperatives and Logic.Alf Ross - 1944 - Philosophy of Science 11 (1):30-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Imperatives and logic.Alf Ross - 1944 - Philosophy of Science 11 (1):30-46.
    The existing literature treats of several investigations with a certain bearing on the question which is roughly indicated by the title “Imperatives and Logic.” Some of those investigations, however, are entirely outside the scope of the present work.Mally sets himself the task of developing a “Logik des Willens” constituting a parallel to the usual logic, the “Logik des Denkens". In order to emphasize its independence, the author also calls this “Logik des Willens” “Deontik”, and he conceives it as being based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Truthmaking, entailment, and the conjunction thesis.Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra - 2006 - Mind 115 (460):957-982.
    In this paper I undermine the Entailment Principle according to which if an entity is a truthmaker for a certain proposition and this proposition entails another, then the entity in question is a truthmaker for the latter proposition. I argue that the two most promising versions of the principle entail the popular but false Conjunction Thesis, namely that a truthmaker for a conjunction is a truthmaker for its conjuncts. One promising version of the principle understands entailment as strict implication but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Non-Assertoric Inference.Robert P. McArthur & David Welker - 1974 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15 (2):225--244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Geach on Murder and Sodomy.R. M. Hare - 1977 - Philosophy 52 (202):467 - 472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The logic of demand-sentences.Rose Rand - 1962 - Synthese 14 (4):237 - 254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logik der Forderungssätze.Rose Rand - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contrary-to-duty obligations.Henry Prakken & Marek Sergot - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):91 - 115.
    We investigate under what conditions contrary-to-duty (CTD) structures lacking temporal and action elements can be given a coherent reading. We argue, contrary to some recent proposals, that CTD is not an instance of defeasible reasoning, and that methods of nonmonotonic logics are inadequate since they are unable to distinguish between defeasibility and violation of primary obligations. We propose a semantic framework based on the idea that primary and CTD obligations are obligations of different kinds: a CTD obligation pertains to, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • What can Logic do for Philosophy?K. R. Popper, W. C. Kneale & A. J. Ayer - 1948 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 22 (1):141-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Knowledge and Justification.John L. Pollock - 1974 - Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Edited by John Pollock.
    Princeton University Press, 1974. This book is out of print, but can be downloaded as a pdf file (5 MB).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Knowledge and Justification.Robert L. Martin - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3):435-436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Defeasible Reasoning.John L. Pollock - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):481-518.
    There was a long tradition in philosophy according to which good reasoning had to be deductively valid. However, that tradition began to be questioned in the 1960’s, and is now thoroughly discredited. What caused its downfall was the recognition that many familiar kinds of reasoning are not deductively valid, but clearly confer justification on their conclusions. Here are some simple examples.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   336 citations  
  • Dernières Pensées.Henri Poincaré - 1920 - CreateSpace.
    "Dernières pensées" de Henri Poincaré. Mathématicien, physicien et philosophe français (1854-1912).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Command and consequence.Josh Parsons - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (1):61-92.
    An argument is usually said to be valid iff it is truth-preserving—iff it cannot be that all its premises are true and its conclusion false. But imperatives (it is normally thought) are not truth-apt. They are not in the business of saying how the world is, and therefore cannot either succeed or fail in doing so. To solve this problem, we need to find a new criterion of validity, and I aim to propose such a criterion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cognitivism about imperatives.Josh Parsons - 2012 - Analysis 72 (1):49-54.
    Cognitivism about imperatives is the thesis that sentences in the imperative mood are truth-apt: have truth values and truth conditions. This allows cognitivists to give a simple and powerful account of consequence relations between imperatives. I argue that this account of imperative consequence has counterexamples that cast doubt on cognitivism itself.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Introduction.Donald Nute - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2):127 - 147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Defeasible Deontic Logic.Donald Nute - 2001 - Studia Logica 67 (1):129-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Imperatives and their logics.Nicholas J. Moutafakis - 1975 - New Delhi: Sterling Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Imperatives and their Logics.Brian F. Chellas - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):375-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poincaré's rule (oder: Wie aus einer schlechten übersetzung eine legende entsteht).Edgar Morscher - 1972 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 10 (3):350-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Der praktische Syllogismus and das juridische Denken.Manfred Moritz - 1954 - Theoria 20 (1-3):78-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Clarke's principle of mood constancy.Edgar Morscher & Gerhard Zecha - 1971 - Philosophia 1 (3-4):209-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Russell's "Theory of Descriptions.".G. E. Moore - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):78-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Truthmakers for negative truths.George Molnar - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (1):72 – 86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The Principle of Mood Constancy.Alfred F. MacKay - 1971 - Analysis 31 (3):91 - 96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The principle of mood constancy.Alfred F. Mackay - 1971 - Analysis 31 (3):91-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations