Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Patterns of Intention: On the Historical Explanation of Pictures.Michael Baxandall - 1986 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45 (1):94-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Cratylus. Plato - 1997 - In J. M. Cooper (ed.), Plato Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett. pp. 101--156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Les Beaux Arts Reduits À Un Même Principe..Charles Batteux - 2019 - Wentworth Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work was reproduced from the original artifact, and remains as true to the original work as possible. Therefore, you will see the original copyright references, library stamps (as most of these works have been housed in our most important libraries around the world), and other notations in the work. This work is in the public domain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Glaring Omissions in Traditional Theories of Art.Peg Zeglin Brand Weiser - 2002 - In Cahn Steven (ed.), Philosophy for the 21st Century: A Comprehensive Reader. Oxford University Press. pp. 799-813.
    I investigate the role of feminist theorizing in relation to traditionally-based aesthetics. Feminist artworks have arisen within the context of a patriarchal Artworld dominated for thousands of years by male artists, critics, theorists, and philosophers. I look at the history of that context as it impacts philosophical theorizing by pinpointing the narrow range of the paradigms used in defining “art.” I test the plausibility of Danto’s After the End of Art vision of a post-historical, pluralistic future in which “anything goes,” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The ‘great divide’ in music.James O. Young - 2005 - British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (2):175-184.
    Several prominent philosophers of music, including Lydia Goehr and Peter Kivy, maintain that the experience of music changed drastically in about 1800. According to the great divide hypothesis, prior to 1800 audiences often scarcely attended to music. At other times, music was appreciated as part of social, civic, or religious ceremonies. After the great divide, audiences began to appreciate music as an exclusive object of aesthetic experience. The great divide hypothesis is false. The musicological record reveals that prior to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Ancient and Modern System of the Arts.James O. Young - 2015 - British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (1):1-17.
    Paul Oskar Kristeller famously argued that the modern ‘ system of the arts ’ did not emerge until the mid-eighteenth century, in the work of Charles Batteux. On this view, the modern conception of the fine arts had no parallel in the ancient world, the middle-ages or the modern period prior to Batteux. This paper argues that Kristeller was wrong. The ancient conception of the imitative arts completely overlaps with Batteux’s fine arts : poetry, painting, music, sculpture, and dance. Writers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The ontology of art and knowledge in aesthetics.Amie L. Thomasson - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (3):221–229.
    Amie L. Thomasson; The Ontology of Art and Knowledge in Aesthetics: Thomasson The Ontology of Art and Knowledge in Aesthetics, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Ordinary Objects.Amie L. Thomasson (ed.) - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Arguments that ordinary inanimate objects such as tables and chairs, sticks and stones, simply do not exist have become increasingly common and increasingly prominent. Some are based on demands for parsimony or for a non-arbitrary answer to the special composition question; others arise from prohibitions against causal redundancy, ontological vagueness, or co-location; and others still come from worries that a common sense ontology would be a rival to a scientific one. Until now, little has been done to address these arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • The Invention of Art: A Cultural History.Larry Shiner - 2003 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (4):401-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • “Primitive Fakes,” “Tourist Art,” and The Ideology of Authenticity.Larry Shiner - 1994 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (2):225-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is Art Modern?James porter - 2009 - BJA 49 (1):1-24.
    Kristeller's article ‘The Modern System of the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics’ is a classic statement of the view, now widely adopted but rarely examined, that aesthetics became possible only in the eighteenth-century with the emergence of the fine arts. I wish to contest this view, for three reasons. Firstly, Kristeller's historical account can be questioned; alternative and equally plausible accounts are available. Secondly, ‘the modern system of the arts’ appears to have been neither a system nor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • What is a theatrical performance?David Osipovich - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4):461–470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Art by another name.David Novitz - 1998 - British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (1):19-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mere Exposure to Bad Art.Aaron Meskin, Mark Phelan, Margaret Moore & Matthew Kieran - 2009 - British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (2):139-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Art Without ‘Art’.Dominic McIver Lopes - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1):1-15.
    Some argue that there is no art in some non-Western cultures because members of those cultures have no concept of art. Others argue that members of some non-Western cultures have concepts of art because they have art. Both arguments assume that if there is art in a given culture, then some members of the culture have a concept of art. There are reasons to think that this assumption is false; and if it is false, there are lessons to learn for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Modern System of the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics.Paul Oskar Kristeller - 1951 - Journal of the History of Ideas 12 (1/4):496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • What Really Happened in the Eighteenth Century: The 'Modern System' Re-examined.P. Kivy - 2012 - British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (1):61-74.
    There is much in James I. Porter's recent critique of Kristeller 's ‘ Modern System of the Arts ’ that is true and enlightening. But something— some things —of great moment in the history of aesthetics and philosophy of art transpired in the age of the Enlightenment, as badly described, and, no doubt, in some ways as badly misdescribed, as they may have been by Kristeller in his account. And it would be a grave disservice to the history of philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The methodology of musical ontology: Descriptivism and its implications.Andrew Kania - 2008 - British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (4):426-444.
    I investigate the widely held view that fundamental musical ontology should be descriptivist rather than revisionary, that is, that it should describe how we think about musical works, rather than how they are independently of our thought about them. I argue that if we take descriptivism seriously then, first, we should be sceptical of art-ontological arguments that appeal to independent metaphysical respectability; and, second, we should give ‘fictionalism’ about musical works—the theory that they do not exist—more serious consideration than it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The imaginary museum of musical works: an essay in the philosophy of music.Lydia Goehr - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What is the difference between a performance of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony and the symphony itself? What does it mean for musicians to be faithful to the works they perform? To answer this question, Goehr combines philosophical and historical methods of enquiry. She describes how the concept of a musical work emerged as late as 1800, and how it subsequently defined the norms, expectations, and behavior characteristic of classical musical practice. Out of the historical thesis, Goehr draws philosophical conclusions about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Paintings and their places.Susan L. Feagin - 1995 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (2):260 – 268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Adventures in the metaontology of art: local descriptivism, artefacts and dreamcatchers.Julian Dodd - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (3):1047-1068.
    Descriptivism in the ontology of art is the thesis that the correct ontological proposal for a kind of artwork cannot show the nascent ontological conception of such things embedded in our critical and appreciative practices to be substantially mistaken. Descriptivists believe that the kinds of revisionary art ontological proposals propounded by Nelson Goodman, Gregory Currie, Mark Sagoff, and me are methodologically misconceived. In this paper I examine the case that has been made for a local form of descriptivism in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The nature of concepts and the definition of art.Jeffrey T. Dean - 2003 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (1):29–35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Balinese aesthetics.Stephen Davies - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (1):21–29.
    According to the Balinese expert, Dr. Anak Agung Mad ´e Djelantik, “no writings about aesthetics specifically as a discipline exist in Bali.”1 The arts are discussed in ancient palm leaf texts, but mainly in connection with religion, spirituality, ceremony, and the like. However, there are famous accounts by expatriate Westerners and anthropologists.2 There have also been collaborations between Balinese and Western scholars.3 In addition, there is a significant literature written in Indonesian by Balinese experts, beginning in the 1970s.4 Considerable experience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Definitions of Art and Fine Art's Historical Origins.David Clowney - 2011 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 69 (3):309-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Historical narratives and the philosophy of art.Noel Carroll - 1993 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3):313-326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Debates about the Ontology of Art: What are We Doing Here?Amie L. Thomasson - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (3):245-255.
    Philosophy Compass, Volume 1. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Art and its objects: with six supplementary essays.Richard Wollheim - 1980 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Richard Thomas Eldridge.
    What defines a work of art and determines the way in which we respond to it? This classic reflection was written with the belief that the nature of art has to be understood simultaneously from the artist's as well as the spectator's viewpoint.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Differencing the Canon: Feminist Desire and the Writing of Art's Histories.Griselda Pollock - 1999 - Psychology Press.
    In this major book, Griselda Pollock engages boldly in the culture wars over `what is the canon?` and `what difference can feminism make?` Do we simply reject the all-male line-up and satisfy our need for ideal egos with an all women litany of artistic heroines? Or is the question a chance to resist the phallocentric binary and allow the ambiguities and complexities of desire - subjectivity and sexuality - to shape the readings of art that constantly displace the present gender (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Art of Theater.James R. Hamilton (ed.) - 2007 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    _The Art of Theater_ argues for the recognition of theatrical performance as an art form independent of dramatic writing. Identifies the elements that make a performance a work of art Looks at the competing views of the text-performance relationships An important and original contribution to the aesthetics and philosophy of theater.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Glaring omissions in traditional theories of art.Peg Zeglin Brand - 1999 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 4:177-186.
    I investigate the role of feminist theorizing in relation to traditionally-based aesthetics. Feminist artworks have arisen within the context of a patriarchal Artworld dominated for thousands of years by male artists, critics, theorists, and philosophers. I look at the history of that context as it impacts philosophical theorizing by pinpointing the narrow range of the paradigms used in defining “art.” I test the plausibility of Danto’s After the End of Art vision of a post-historical, pluralistic future in which “anything goes,” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mythologies of Tribal Art.Denis Dutton - unknown
    Forty years ago Roland Barthes defined a mythology as those “falsely obvious” ideas which an age so takes for granted that it is unaware of its own belief. An illustration of what he meant can be seen in his 1957 critique of the photographic exhibition, The Family of Man . Barthes declares that the myth it promotes stresses exoticism, complacently projecting a Babel of human diversity over the globe. From this image of diversity a pluralistic humanism “is magically produced: man (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Non-Western Art and the Concept of Art: Can Cluster Theories of Art Account for the Universality of Art?Annelies Monseré - 2012 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 49 (2):148-165.
    This essay seeks to demonstrate that there are no compelling reasons to exclude non-Western artefacts from the domain of art. Any theory of art must therefore account for the universality of the concept of art. It cannot simply start from ‘our’ art traditions and extend these conceptions to other cultures, since this would imply cultural appropriation, nor can it resolve the matter simply by formulating separate criteria for non-Western art, since this would imply that there is no unity in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability.Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman - 1973 - Cognitive Psychology 5 (2):207-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   273 citations  
  • Exposure and affect: Overview and meta-analysis of research 1968-1987.Robert F. Bornstein - 1989 - Psychological Bulletin 106:265-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations