Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The reality of the symbolic and subsymbolic systems.Andrew Woodfield & Adam Morton - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):58-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensitive and insensitive causation.James Woodward - 2006 - Philosophical Review 115 (1):1-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Complexity, guided search, and the data.Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):457-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Circulatory behavior: Historical perspective and projections for the future.Stewart Wolf - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):304-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where's the psychological reality?C. Philip Winder - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):417-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strategies for goal-directed fast movements are byproducts of satisfying performance criteria.Jack M. Winters & Amir H. Seif-Naraghi - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):357-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cartesian vs. Newtonian research strategies for cognitive science.Morton E. Winston - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):463-464.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Realization: Metaphysics, mind, and science.Robert A. Wilson - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):985-996.
    This paper surveys some recent work on realization in the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Rules are not processes.Robert Wilensky - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The mystery-mastery-imagery complex.H. T. A. Whiting & R. P. Ingvaldsen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):228-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tactical deception in primates.A. Whiten & R. W. Byrne - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):233-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Channeling knowledge: Expert Systems as communications media. [REVIEW]Randall Whitaker & Olov Östberg - 1988 - AI and Society 2 (3):197-208.
    Expert Systems (ES) are as yet imperfectly defined. Their two consistently cited characteristics are domain knowledge and expert-level performance. We propose that current structural definitions are inadequate and suggest a view of ES as communication channels. We proceed to explore the factors influencing applicability of ES technology to an enterprise and the impacts that could be expected. A consequence of this view is the idea of incremental information loss on the path from the expert to the ES user. Strategies for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A perspective for viewing the present of psychophysics.Paul Whittle - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):165-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genic representation: Reconciling content and causal complexity.M. Wheeler & A. Clark - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (1):103-135.
    Some recent cognitive-scientific research suggests that a considerable amount of intelligent action is generated not by the systematic activity of internal representations, but by complex interactions involving neural, bodily, and environmental factors. Following an analysis of this threat to representational explanation, we pursue an analogy between the role of genes in the production of biological form and the role of neural states in the production of behaviour, in order to develop a notion of genic representation. In both cases an appeal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Cognition and simulation.N. E. Wetherick - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):462-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition as self–organizing process.Gerhard Werner - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):183-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Turing's Analysis of Computation and Theories of Cognitive Architecture.A. J. Wells - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):269-294.
    Turing's analysis of computation is a fundamental part of the background of cognitive science. In this paper it is argued that a re‐interpretation of Turing's work is required to underpin theorizing about cognitive architecture. It is claimed that the symbol systems view of the mind, which is the conventional way of understanding how Turing's work impacts on cognitive science, is deeply flawed. There is an alternative interpretation that is more faithful to Turing's original insights, avoids the criticisms made of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Situated action, symbol systems and universal computation.Andrew Wells - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6 (1):33-46.
    Vera & Simon (1993a) have argued that the theories and methods known as situated action or situativity theory are compatible with the assumptions and methodology of the physical symbol systems hypothesis and do not require a new approach to the study of cognition. When the central criterion of computational universality is added to the loose definition of a symbol system which Vera and Simon provide, it becomes apparent that there are important incompatibilities between the two approaches such that situativity theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The place of time in cognition.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2004 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (1):87-105.
    models of cognition are essentially incomplete because they fail to capture the temporal properties of mental processing. I present two possible interpretations of the dynamicists' argument from time and show that neither one is successful. The disagreement between dynamicists and symbolic theorists rests not on temporal considerations per se, but on differences over the multiple realizability of cognitive states and the proper explanatory goals of psychology. The negative arguments of dynamicists against symbolic models fail, and it is doubtful whether pursuing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The origins of concepts.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 140 (3):359 - 384.
    Certain of our concepts are innate, but many others are learned. Despite the plausibility of this claim, some have argued that the very idea of concept learning is incoherent. I present a conception of learning that sidesteps the arguments against the possibility of concept learning, and sketch several mechanisms that result in the generation of new primitive concepts. Given the rational considerations that motivate their deployment, I argue that these deserve to be called learning mechanisms. I conclude by replying to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The creative mind versus the creative computer.Robert W. Weisberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Looking backward: Progress in outer psychophysics.David J. Weiss - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):165-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Closing the chinese room.Timothy Weiss - 1990 - Ratio 3 (2):165-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Closing the Chinese Room.Thomas Weiss - 2006 - Ratio 3 (2):165-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Knowledge of counterfactual interventions through cognitive models of mechanisms.Jonathan Waskan - 2008 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (3):259 – 275.
    Here I consider the relative merits of two recent models of explanation, James Woodward's interventionist-counterfactual model and the model model. According to the former, explanations are largely constituted by information about the consequences of counterfactual interventions. Problems arise for this approach because countless relevant interventions are possible in most cases and because it overlooks other kinds of equally relevant information. According the model model, explanations are largely constituted by cognitive models of actual mechanisms. On this approach, explanations tend not to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Intrinsic cognitive models.Jonathan A. Waskan - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (2):259-283.
    Theories concerning the structure, or format, of mental representation should (1) be formulated in mechanistic, rather than metaphorical terms; (2) do justice to several philosophical intuitions about mental representation; and (3) explain the human capacity to predict the consequences of worldly alterations (i.e., to think before we act). The hypothesis that thinking involves the application of syntax-sensitive inference rules to syntactically structured mental representations has been said to satisfy all three conditions. An alternative hypothesis is that thinking requires the construction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Potential disparities between imagining and preparing motor skills.Charles B. Walter & Stephan P. Swinnen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):227-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A brief history of connectionism and its psychological implications.S. F. Walker - 1990 - AI and Society 4 (1):17-38.
    Critics of the computational connectionism of the last decade suggest that it shares undesirable features with earlier empiricist or associationist approaches, and with behaviourist theories of learning. To assess the accuracy of this charge the works of earlier writers are examined for the presence of such features, and brief accounts of those found are given for Herbert Spencer, William James and the learning theorists Thorndike, Pavlov and Hull. The idea that cognition depends on associative connections among large networks of neurons (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the construction of psychophysical reality.Mark Wagner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):164-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is extension to perception of real-world objects and scenes possible?J. Wagemans, K. Verfaillie, P. De Graef & K. Lamberts - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):415-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The explanatory need for mental representations in cognitive science.Barbara Von Eckardt - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):427-439.
    Ramsey (1997) argues that connectionist representations 'do not earn their explanatory keep'. The aim of this paper is to examine the argument Ramsey gives to support that conclusion. In doing so, I identify two kinds of explanatory need—need relative to a possible explanation and need relative to a true explanation and argue that internal representations are not needed for either connectionist or nonconnectionist possible explanations but that it is quite likely that they are needed for true explanations. However, to show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mental images and their explanations.Barbara Von Eckardt - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (3):691-693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental images and their explanations.Barbara von Eckardt - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (11):691-693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imagery needs preparation too.Stefan Vogt - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):226-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neural Representation. A Survey-Based Analysis of the Notion.Oscar Vilarroya - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Autopoiesis, Life, Mind and Cognition: Bases for a Proper Naturalistic Continuity. [REVIEW]Mario Villalobos - 2013 - Biosemiotics 6 (3):379-391.
    The strong version of the life-mind continuity thesis claims that mind can be understood as an enriched version of the same functional and organizational properties of life. Contrary to this view, in this paper I argue that mental phenomena offer distinctive properties, such as intentionality or representational content, that have no counterpart in the phenomenon of life, and that must be explained by appealing to a different level of functional and organizational principles. As a strategy, and following Maturana’s autopoietic theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On putting the cart before the horse: Taking perception seriously in unified theories of cognition.Kim J. Vicente & Alex Kirlik - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):461-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Smolensky's theory of mind.Paul F. M. J. Verschure - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):407-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial Representations Elicit Dual‐Coding Effects in Mental Imagery.Michelle Verges & Sean Duffy - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (6):1157-1172.
    Spatial aspects of words are associated with their canonical locations in the real world. Yet little research has tested whether spatial associations denoted in language comprehension generalize to their corresponding images. We directly tested the spatial aspects of mental imagery in picture and word processing (Experiment 1). We also tested whether spatial representations of motion words produce similar perceptual-interference effects as demonstrated by object words (Experiment 2). Findings revealed that words denoting an upward spatial location produced slower responses to targets (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Levels of Explanation Vindicated.Víctor M. Verdejo & Daniel Quesada - 2011 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (1):77-88.
    Marr’s celebrated contribution to cognitive science (Marr 1982, chap. 1) was the introduction of (at least) three levels of description/explanation. However, most contemporary research has relegated the distinction between levels to a rather dispensable remark. Ignoring such an important contribution comes at a price, or so we shall argue. In the present paper, first we review Marr’s main points and motivations regarding levels of explanation. Second, we examine two cases in which the distinction between levels has been neglected when considering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A cognitive process shell.Steven A. Vere - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):460-461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The limits of neuropsychological models of consciousness.Max Velmans - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):702-703.
    This commentary elaborates on Gray's conclusion that his neurophysiological model of consciousness might explain how consciousness arises from the brain, but does not address how consciousness evolved, affects behaviour or confers survival value. The commentary argues that such limitations apply to all neurophysiological or other third-person perspective models. To approach such questions the first-person nature of consciousness needs to be taken seriously in combination with third-person models of the brain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Common sense, functional theories and knowledge of the mind.Max Velmans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):85-86.
    A commentary on a target article by Alison Gopnik (1993) How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Focusing on evidence of how children acquire a theory of mind, this commentary argues that there are internal inconsistencies in theories that both argue for the functional role of conscious experiences and the irreducibility of those experiences to third-person viewable information processing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On observing emergent properties and their compositions.Francisco T. Varela & Vicente Sanchez-Leighton - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):401-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criteria for the Design and Evaluation of Cognitive Architectures.Sashank Varma - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (7):1329-1351.
    Cognitive architectures are unified theories of cognition that take the form of computational formalisms. They support computational models that collectively account for large numbers of empirical regularities using small numbers of computational mechanisms. Empirical coverage and parsimony are the most prominent criteria by which architectures are designed and evaluated, but they are not the only ones. This paper considers three additional criteria that have been comparatively undertheorized. (a) Successful architectures possess subjective and intersubjective meaning, making cognition comprehensible to individual cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The roles of philosophy in cognitive science.Tim Van Gelder - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (2):117-36.
    When the various disciplines participating in cognitive science are listed, philosophy almost always gets a guernsey. Yet, a couple of years ago at the conference of the Cognitive Science Society in Boulder (USA), there was no philosophy or philosopher with any prominence on the program. When queried on this point, the organizer (one of the "superstars" of the field) claimed it was partly an accident, but partly also due to an impression among members of the committee that philosophy is basically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The embedded view, its critics, and a radically non-representational solution.Thomas van Es - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 1):195-211.
    Whether perception involves the manipulation of representations is currently heavily debated. The embedded view advanced by Nico Orlandi seeks a middle passage between representationalism and radical enactivism. In this paper I argue for a non-representational take on EV. I argue that this is the best way to resolve the objections EV has received from both representationalists and non-representationalists. I analyze this debate, and distinguish four sorts of objections: the objection of the wrongfully cut middleman, the argument against explanatory exclusionism, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Tim van Gelder - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):615-28.
    According to the dominant computational approach in cognitive science, cognitive agents are digital computers; according to the alternative approach, they are dynamical systems. This target article attempts to articulate and support the dynamical hypothesis. The dynamical hypothesis has two major components: the nature hypothesis (cognitive agents are dynamical systems) and the knowledge hypothesis (cognitive agents can be understood dynamically). A wide range of objections to this hypothesis can be rebutted. The conclusion is that cognitive systems may well be dynamical systems, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • The analysis of sensations as the foundation of all sciences.J. van Brakel - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):163-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Syntactic processes in speech production: the retrieval of grammatical gender.Jos J. A. van Berkum - 1997 - Cognition 64 (2):115-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations