Switch to: Citations

References in:

In defense of content-independence

Legal Theory 23 (3):143-167 (2017)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths.John Gardner - 2001 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 46 (1):199-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Content-Independence of Political Obligations.Kevin Walton - 2014 - Political Theory 42 (2):218-222.
    George Klosko rejects the standard assumption that political obligations, at least insofar as they are conceived as moral requirements to obey the law, must be content-independent. He thereby neglects the familiar distinction between obedience to and mere compliance with legal norms. The present article insists on this distinction by identifying a plausible alternative to the understanding of content-independence that Klosko correctly, even if not for the most obvious reason, dismisses and mistakenly, though not unreasonably, attributes to several philosophers with whose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Democratic Equality and Political Authority.Daniel Viehoff - 2014 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (4):337-375.
    This essay seeks to provide a justification for the ‘egalitarian authority claim’, according to which citizens of democratic states have a moral duty to obey (at least some) democratically made laws because they are the outcome of an egalitarian procedure. It begins by considering two prominent arguments that link democratic authority to a concern for equality. Both are ultimately unsuccessful; but their failures are instructive, and help identify the conditions that a plausible defense of the egalitarian authority claim must meet. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • On Hart's Way Out.Scott J. Shapiro - 1998 - Legal Theory 4 (4):469-507.
    It is hard to think of a more banal statement one could make about the law than to say that it necessarily claims legal authority to govern conduct. What, after all, is a legal institution if not an entity that purports to have the legal power to create rules, confer rights, and impose obligations? Whether legal institutions necessarily claim the moral authority to exercise their legal powers is another question entirely. Some legal theorists have thought that they do—others have not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On Hart's Way Out.Scott J. Shapiro - 1998 - Legal Theory 4 (4):469-507.
    It is hard to think of a more banal statement one could make about the law than to say that it necessarily claims legal authority to govern conduct. What, after all, is a legal institution if not an entity that purports to have the legal power to create rules, confer rights, and impose obligations? Whether legal institutions necessarily claim themoralauthority to exercise their legal powers is another question entirely. Some legal theorists have thought that they do—others have not been so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Content-Independent Reasons: It’s Not in the Name.Stefan Sciaraffa - 2009 - Law and Philosophy 28 (3):233 - 260.
    Argues that content-independent reasons are intentions. Relies on Grice's distinction between natural and non-natural meaning. Rejects previous accounts, and argues that his account can understand the force of such reasons appropriately, through the conept of enabling-conditions. Illustrates through several paridigmatic types of content-independent reasons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Law and Content-Independent Reasons.P. Markwick - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (4):579-596.
    Say a reason to ø is legal just in case at least a part of the reason is the fact that ø-ing is legally required. This paper is about the widely accepted claim that legal reasons have a certain distinctive formal property—content-independence. I argue that, on two important interpretations, this claim is false. It is false either because legal reasons contingently lack the relevant property or because no reason lacks it. I also argue that, given these two interpretations, content-independence could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Independent of content.P. Markwick - 2003 - Legal Theory 9 (1):43-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Authorities and Persons.Andrei Marmor - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (3):337-359.
    In this article I want to support a certain conception of legal authority. The question I want to address is this: Is it possible to attribute legal authority to a given norm if its authority does not derive from the authority of someone who has issued that norm? Basically, I will try to defend here a negative answer to this question, espousing a personal conception of authority.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Rule Over None II: Social Equality and the Justification of Democracy.Niko Kolodny - 2014 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (4):287-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Rule Over None I: What Justifies Democracy?Niko Kolodny - 2014 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (3):195-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Content-Independent Obligations.George Klosko - 2014 - Political Theory 42 (2):223-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Are Political Obligations Content Independent?George Klosko - 2011 - Political Theory 39 (4):498-523.
    Current scholars generally view political obligations as "content independent." Citizens have moral reasons to obey the law because it is the law, rather than because of the content of different laws. However, this position is subject to criticism on both theoretical and practical grounds. The main consideration in favor of content independence, the so-called "self-image of the state," does not actually support it. Properly understood, the state's self-image is to comply with laws because of the underlying moral reasons that justify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • H.l.A. Hart and the practical difference thesis.Kenneth Einar Himma - 2000 - Legal Theory 6 (1):1-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Experts: Which ones should you trust?Alvin I. Goldman - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1):85-110.
    Mainstream epistemology is a highly theoretical and abstract enterprise. Traditional epistemologists rarely present their deliberations as critical to the practical problems of life, unless one supposes—as Hume, for example, did not—that skeptical worries should trouble us in our everyday affairs. But some issues in epistemology are both theoretically interesting and practically quite pressing. That holds of the problem to be discussed here: how laypersons should evaluate the testimony of experts and decide which of two or more rival experts is most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   357 citations  
  • LEGAL POSITIVISM: 5 1/2 MYTHS.John Gardner - 2001 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 46 (1):199-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The authority of democracy.Thomas Christiano - 2004 - Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (3):266–290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Trust and antitrust.Annette Baier - 1986 - Ethics 96 (2):231-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   592 citations  
  • Are Legal Rules Content-Independent Reasons?Noam Gur - 2011 - Problema 5:175-210.
    I argue that the answer to the above question turns on three distinctions as to the meaning of content-independent reasons and the types of statement in which they feature. The first distinction is between two senses of content-independence, which I refer to as weak and strong content-independence. I argue that, while legal rules can (and often do) give rise to content-independent reasons in the weak sense, whether they can be said to generate content-independent reasons in the strong sense depends on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations