Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Herbrand's theorem and term induction.Matthias Baaz & Georg Moser - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (4):447-503.
    We study the formal first order system TIND in the standard language of Gentzen's LK . TIND extends LK by the purely logical rule of term-induction, that is a restricted induction principle, deriving numerals instead of arbitrary terms. This rule may be conceived as the logical image of full induction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)2000 Annual Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.A. Pillay, D. Hallett, G. Hjorth, C. Jockusch, A. Kanamori, H. J. Keisler & V. McGee - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):361-396.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Describing proofs by short tautologies.Stefan Hetzl - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 159 (1-2):129-145.
    Herbrand’s theorem is one of the most fundamental results about first-order logic. In the context of proof analysis, Herbrand-disjunctions are used for describing the constructive content of cut-free proofs. However, given a proof with cuts, the computation of a Herbrand-disjunction is of significant computational complexity, as the cuts in the proof have to be eliminated first.In this paper we prove a generalization of Herbrand’s theorem: From a proof with cuts, one can read off a small tautology composed of instances of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sufficient conditions for cut elimination with complexity analysis.João Rasga - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 149 (1-3):81-99.
    Sufficient conditions for first-order-based sequent calculi to admit cut elimination by a Schütte–Tait style cut elimination proof are established. The worst case complexity of the cut elimination is analysed. The obtained upper bound is parameterized by a quantity related to the calculus. The conditions are general enough to be satisfied by a wide class of sequent calculi encompassing, among others, some sequent calculi presentations for the first order and the propositional versions of classical and intuitionistic logic, classical and intuitionistic modal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Sharpened lower bounds for cut elimination.Samuel R. Buss - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):656-668.
    We present sharpened lower bounds on the size of cut free proofs for first-order logic. Prior lower bounds for eliminating cuts from a proof established superexponential lower bounds as a stack of exponentials, with the height of the stack proportional to the maximum depth d of the formulas in the original proof. Our results remove the constant of proportionality, giving an exponential stack of height equal to d — 0(1). The proof method is based on more efficiently expressing the Gentzen-Solovay (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unsound inferences make proofs shorter.Juan P. Aguilera & Matthias Baaz - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):102-122.
    We give examples of calculi that extend Gentzen’s sequent calculusLKby unsound quantifier inferences in such a way that derivations lead only to true sequents, and proofs therein are nonelementarily shorter thanLK-proofs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the complexity of proof deskolemization.Matthias Baaz, Stefan Hetzl & Daniel Weller - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):669-686.
    We consider the following problem: Given a proof of the Skolemization of a formula F, what is the length of the shortest proof of F? For the restriction of this question to cut-free proofs we prove corresponding exponential upper and lower bounds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations