Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Why circumcision is a biomedical imperative for the 21 st century.Brian J. Morris - 2007 - Bioessays 29 (11):1147-1158.
    Circumcision of males represents a surgical “vaccine“ against a wide variety of infections, adverse medical conditions and potentially fatal diseases over their lifetime, and also protects their sexual partners. In experienced hands, this common, inexpensive procedure is very safe, can be pain‐free and can be performed at any age. The benefits vastly outweigh risks. The enormous public health benefits include protection from urinary tract infections, sexually transmitted HIV, HPV, syphilis and chancroid, penile and prostate cancer, phimosis, thrush, and inflammatory dermatoses. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Infant circumcision: the last stand for the dead dogma of parental (sovereignal) rights.Robert S. Van Howe - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):475-481.
    J S Mill used the term ‘dead dogma’ to describe a belief that has gone unquestioned for so long and to such a degree that people have little idea why they accept it or why they continue to believe it. When wives and children were considered chattel, it made sense for the head of a household to have a ‘sovereignal right’ to do as he wished with his property. Now that women and children are considered to have the full complement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Evaluations of circumcision should be circumscribed by the evidence.David Benatar - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):431-432.
    One common mistake in discussions about the ethics of infant male circumcisioni is to attempt to answer the question of the practice's permissibility by appealing to general principles and bypassing the empirical evidence about purported benefits and harms of the practice.Joseph Mazor1 avoids the mistake of appealing only to general principles. He correctly argues that it is not sufficient to invoke a child's right to bodily integrity or to self-determinationii. Moreover, he does not appeal to parents’ rights to religious or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Standards for Family Decisions: Replacing Best Interests with Harm Prevention.Rebecca Dresser - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):54-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Ethics of Neonatal Male Circumcision: A Catholic Perspective.John Paul Slosar & Daniel O'Brien - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):62-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • I Paid Out-of-Pocket for My Son's Circumcision at Happy Valley Tattoo and Piercing: Alternative Framings of the Debate over Routine Neonatal Male Circumcision.Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):50-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Circumcision—A Victorian Relic Lacking Ethical, Medical, or Legal Justification.J. Steven Svoboda - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):52-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Circumcision as human-rights violation: Assessing Benatar and Benatar.Rio Cruz, Leonard B. Glick & John W. Travis - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):19 – 20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Male neonatal circumcision: Ritual or public-health imperative.Frances R. Batzer & Joshua M. Hurwitz - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):26 – 27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Child’s Right to Bodily Integrity: When Is the Right Infringed?Joseph Mazor - 2021 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 46 (4):451-465.
    This article considers two competing types of conceptions of the pre-autonomous child’s right to bodily integrity. The first, which I call encroachment conceptions, holds that any physically serious bodily encroachment infringes on the child’s right to bodily integrity. The second, which I call best-interests conceptions, holds that the child’s right to bodily integrity is infringed just in case the child is subjected to a bodily encroachment that substantially deviates from what is in the child’s best interests. I argue in this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Male or female genital cutting: why ‘health benefits’ are morally irrelevant.Brian D. Earp - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (12):e92-e92.
    The WHO, American Academy of Pediatrics and other Western medical bodies currently maintain that all medically unnecessary female genital cutting of minors is categorically a human rights violation, while either tolerating or actively endorsing medically unnecessary male genital cutting of minors, especially in the form of penile circumcision. Given that some forms of female genital cutting, such as ritual pricking or nicking of the clitoral hood, are less severe than penile circumcision, yet are often performed within the same families for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Female genital alteration: a compromise solution.Kavita Shah Arora & Allan J. Jacobs - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (3):148-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Circumcision, Autonomy and Public Health.Brian D. Earp & Robert Darby - 2019 - Public Health Ethics 12 (1):64-81.
    Male circumcision—partial or total removal of the penile prepuce—has been proposed as a public health measure in Sub-Saharan Africa, based on the results of three randomized control trials showing a relative risk reduction of approximately 60 per cent for voluntary, adult male circumcision against female-to-male human immunodeficiency virus transmission in that context. More recently, long-time advocates of infant male circumcision have argued that these findings justify involuntary circumcision of babies and children in dissimilar public health environments, such as the USA, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Newborn Male Circumcision with Parental Consent, as Stated in the AAP Circumcision Policy Statement, Is Both Legal and Ethical.Michael T. Brady - 2016 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 44 (2):256-262.
    Newborn male circumcision is a minor surgical procedure that has generated significant controversy. Accumulating evidence supports significant health benefits, most notably reductions in urinary tract infections, acquisition of HIV and a number of other sexually transmitted infections, penile cancer, phimosis, paraphimosis, balanitis and lichen sclerosis. While circumcision, like any surgical procedure, has risks for complications, they occur in less than 1 in 500 infants circumcised and most are minor and require minimal intervention. The CDC and the American Academy of Pediatrics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Female genital mutilation and male circumcision: toward an autonomy-based ethical framework.Brian Earp - forthcoming - Medicolegal and Bioethics:89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ritual Male Infant Circumcision and Human Rights.Allan J. Jacobs & Kavita Shah Arora - 2015 - American Journal of Bioethics 15 (2):30-39.
    Opponents of male circumcision have increasingly used human rights positions to articulate their viewpoint. We characterize the meaning of the term “human rights.” We discuss these human rights arguments with special attention to the claims of rights to an open future and to bodily integrity. We offer a three-part test under which a parental decision might be considered an unacceptable violation of a child's right. The test considers the impact of the practice on society, the impact of the practice on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Can Culture Justify Infant Circumcision?Eldar Sarajlic - 2014 - Res Publica 20 (4):327-343.
    The paper addresses arguments in the recent philosophical and bioethical literature claiming that social and cultural benefits can justify non-therapeutic male infant circumcision. It rejects these claims by referring to the open future argument, according to which infant circumcision is morally unjustifiable because it violates the child’s right to an open future. The paper also addresses an important objection to the open future argument and examines the strength of the objection to refute the application of the argument to the circumcision (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Parenthood and Procreation.Tim Bayne & Avery Kolers - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Circumcision, sexual dysfunction and the child's best interests: why the anatomical details matter.David P. Lang - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):429-431.
    In his contribution to the Journal of Medical Ethics, Joseph Mazor1 makes a logical case, based on the premises underlying his reasoning, for his article's primary thesis: he concludes that parents have the prerogative to determine the ‘best interests’ of their infant son in a circumcision decision. If the facts of the matter were ultimately no different from what he adduces, one could admit the soundness of his argument. But the paper is flawed by some questionable assumptions and grievous incompleteness.First, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The child's interests and the case for the permissibility of male infant circumcision: Table 1.Joseph Mazor - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):421-428.
    Circumcision of a male child was recently ruled illegal by a court in Germany on the grounds that it violates the child's rights to bodily integrity and self-determination. This paper begins by challenging the applicability of these rights to the circumcision debate. It argues that, rather than a sweeping appeal to rights, a moral analysis of the practice of circumcision will require a careful examination of the interests of the child. I consider three of these interests in some detail. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Doctors, dying children and religious parents: dialogue or demonization?David Albert Jones, David R. Katz & John Wyatt - 2013 - Clinical Ethics 8 (1):2-4.
    A recent online article in the Journal of Medical Ethics, which received wide media coverage, raised the possibility that children are being ‘subjected to torture’ due to the ‘fervent or fundamentalist views’ of their parents. However, the quality of argument in that article was inadequate to sustain such a radical thesis. There was no engagement with the perspectives of different religious traditions about end-of-life care. Instead the authors invoked practices such as male infant circumcision which are wholly irrelevant to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Physician Obligation, Cultural Factors, and Neonatal Male Circumcision.Paul J. Ford - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):58-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neonatal Male Circumcision: Ethical Issues and Physician Responsibility.Caroline McGee Jones - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):59-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What Is Mutilation?Nicholas C. Lund-Molfese - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):64-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Social Norm Theory and Male Circumcision: Why Parents Circumcise.Sarah E. Waldeck - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):56-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Male circumcision and HIV prevention: ethical, medical and public health tradeoffs in low-income countries.S. Rennie, A. S. Muula & D. Westreich - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (6):357-361.
    Ethical challenges surrounding the implementation of male circumcision as an HIV prevention strategyResearchers have been exploring the possibility of a correlation between male circumcision and lowered risk of HIV infection almost since the beginning of the HIV/AIDS epidemic.1 Results from a randomised controlled trial in South Africa in 2005 indicate that male circumcision protects men against the acquisition of HIV through heterosexual intercourse,2 confirming the findings from 20 years of observational studies.3 Circumcised men in the South African trial were 60% (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Nontherapeutic circumcision is ethically bankrupt.Wayne F. Hampton - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):21 – 22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Respect for bodily integrity: A catholic perspective on circumcision in catholic hospitals.Petrina Fadel - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):23 – 25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cultural bias in responses to male and female genital surgeries.Dena S. Davis - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • 3:2 target article authors respond to commentators: How not to argue about circumcision.David Benatar & Michael Benatar - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):1 – 9.
    Opinion about neonatal male circumcision is deeply divided. Some take it to be a prophylactic measure with unequivocal and significant health benefits, while others consider it a form of child abuse. We argue against both these polar views. In doing so, we discuss whether circumcision constitutes bodily mutilation, whether the absence of the child's informed consent makes it wrong, the nature and strength of the evidence regarding medical harms and benefits, and what moral weight cultural considerations have. We conclude that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Infant circumcision: the last stand for the dead dogma of parental (sovereignal) rights.R. S. Howe - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):475-481.
    J S Mill used the term ‘dead dogma’ to describe a belief that has gone unquestioned for so long and to such a degree that people have little idea why they accept it or why they continue to believe it. When wives and children were considered chattel, it made sense for the head of a household to have a ‘sovereignal right’ to do as he wished with his property. Now that women and children are considered to have the full complement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cutting History, Cutting Culture: Female Circumcision in the United States.Sarah Webber & Toby Schonfeld - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A covenant with the status quo? Male circumcision and the new BMA guidance to doctors.M. Fox - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (8):463-469.
    This article offers a critique of the recently revised BMA guidance on routine neonatal male circumcision and seeks to challenge the assumptions underpinning the guidance which construe this procedure as a matter of parental choice. Our aim is to problematise continued professional willingness to tolerate the non-therapeutic, non-consensual excision of healthy tissue, arguing that in this context both professional guidance and law are uncharacteristically tolerant of risks inflicted on young children, given the absence of clear medical benefits. By interrogating historical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Non-therapeutic penile circumcision of minors: current controversies in UK law and medical ethics.Antony Lempert, James Chegwidden, Rebecca Steinfeld & Brian D. Earp - 2023 - Clinical Ethics 18 (1):36-54.
    The current legal status and medical ethics of routine or religious penile circumcision of minors is a matter of ongoing controversy in many countries. We focus on the United Kingdom as an illustrative example, giving a detailed analysis of the most recent British Medical Association guidance from 2019. We argue that the guidance paints a confused and conflicting portrait of the law and ethics of the procedure in the UK context, reflecting deeper, unresolved moral and legal tensions surrounding child genital (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Infant male circumcision and the autonomy of the child: two ethical questions.Akim McMath - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (8):687-690.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the impermissibility of infant male circumcision: a response to Mazor.Eliyahu Ungar-Sargon - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (2):186-190.
    This is a response to Dr Joseph Mazor’s paper ‘The child's interests and the case for the permissibility of male infant circumcision.’ I argue that Dr Mazor fails to prove that bodily integrity and self-determination are mere interests as opposed to genuine rights in the case of infant male circumcision. Moreover, I cast doubt on the interest calculus that Dr Mazor employs to arrive at his conclusions about circumcision.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Medical, religious and social reasons for and against an ancient rite.Bennett Foddy - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):415-415.
    This month's issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics is a special issue devoted entirely to the ethics of infant male circumcision—an elective surgical practice that is currently performed on around a third of the world's male population.1The last time the Journal ran a symposium on this issue was in 2004, and there has been relatively scant discussion of the practice in the ethical literature since then. Three events that took place in the past year have brought the ethics of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Male Circumcision, Religious Preferences, and the Question of Harm.Mark Sheldon - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):61-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who Speaks for Sons?Michelle A. Mullen - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can anyone authorize the nontherapeutic permanent alteration of a child's body?George Hill - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):16 – 18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark