Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Minimal from classical proofs.Helmut Schwichtenberg & Christoph Senjak - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (6):740-748.
    Let A be a formula without implications, and Γ consist of formulas containing disjunction and falsity only negatively and implication only positively. Orevkov and Nadathur proved that classical derivability of A from Γ implies intuitionistic derivability, by a transformation of derivations in sequent calculi. We give a new proof of this result , where the input data are natural deduction proofs in long normal form involving stability axioms for relations; the proof gives a quadratic algorithm to remove the stability axioms. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The λ μ T -calculus.Herman Geuvers, Robbert Krebbers & James McKinna - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (6):676-701.
    Calculi with control operators have been studied as extensions of simple type theory. Real programming languages contain datatypes, so to really understand control operators, one should also include these in the calculus. As a first step in that direction, we introduce λμTλμT, a combination of Parigotʼs λμ-calculus and Gödelʼs T, to extend a calculus with control operators with a datatype of natural numbers with a primitive recursor.We consider the problem of confluence on raw terms, and that of strong normalization for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Light monotone Dialectica methods for proof mining.Mircea-Dan Hernest - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (5):551-561.
    In view of an enhancement of our implementation on the computer, we explore the possibility of an algorithmic optimization of the various proof-theoretic techniques employed by Kohlenbach for the synthesis of new effective uniform bounds out of established qualitative proofs in Numerical Functional Analysis. Concretely, we prove that the method of “colouring” some of the quantifiers as “non-computational” extends well to ε-arithmetization, elimination-of-extensionality and model-interpretation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negative Translations Not Intuitionistically Equivalent to the Usual Ones.Jaime Gaspar - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (1):45-63.
    We refute the conjecture that all negative translations are intuitionistically equivalent by giving two counterexamples. Then we characterise the negative translations intuitionistically equivalent to the usual ones.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Programs from proofs using classical dependent choice.Monika Seisenberger - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 153 (1-3):97-110.
    This article generalises the refined A-translation method for extracting programs from classical proofs [U. Berger,W. Buchholz, H. Schwichtenberg, Refined program extraction from classical proofs, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 114 3–25] to the scenario where additional assumptions such as choice principles are involved. In the case of choice principles, this is done by adding computational content to the ‘translated’ assumptions, an idea which goes back to [S. Berardi, M. Bezem, T. Coquand, On the computational content of the axiom of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Uniform heyting arithmetic.Ulrich Berger - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 133 (1):125-148.
    We present an extension of Heyting arithmetic in finite types called Uniform Heyting Arithmetic that allows for the extraction of optimized programs from constructive and classical proofs. The system has two sorts of first-order quantifiers: ordinary quantifiers governed by the usual rules, and uniform quantifiers subject to stronger variable conditions expressing roughly that the quantified object is not computationally used in the proof. We combine a Kripke-style Friedman/Dragalin translation which is inspired by work of Coquand and Hofmann and a variant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Dialectica interpretation of well-founded induction.Helmut Schwichtenberg - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (3):229-239.
    From a classical proof that the gcd of natural numbers a1 and a2 is a linear combination of the two, we extract by Gödel's Dialectica interpretation an algorithm computing the coefficients. The proof uses the minimum principle. We show generally how well-founded recursion can be used to Dialectica interpret well-founded induction, which is needed in the proof of the minimum principle. In the special case of the example above it turns out that we obtain a reasonable extracted term, representing an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Light dialectica revisited.Mircea-Dan Hernest & Trifon Trifonov - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (11):1379-1389.
    We upgrade the light Dialectica interpretation [6] by adding two more light universal quantifiers, which are both semi-computational and semi-uniform and complement each other. An illustrative example is presented for the new light quantifiers and a new application is given for the older uniform quantifier. The realizability of new light negative formulations for the Axiom of Choice and for the Independence of Premises is explored in the new setting.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 2004 Annual Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Sergei Artemov - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (1):92-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark