Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The simplest protoalgebraic logic.Josep Maria Font - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (6):435-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Coalgebraic Perspective on Logical Interpretations.M. A. Martins, A. Madeira & L. S. Barbosa - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (4):783-825.
    In Computer Science stepwise refinement of algebraic specifications is a well-known formal methodology for rigorous program development. This paper illustrates how techniques from Algebraic Logic, in particular that of interpretation, understood as a multifunction that preserves and reflects logical consequence, capture a number of relevant transformations in the context of software design, reuse, and adaptation, difficult to deal with in classical approaches. Examples include data encapsulation and the decomposition of operations into atomic transactions. But if interpretations open such a new (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Categorical Abstract Algebraic Logic: Truth-Equational $pi$-Institutions.George Voutsadakis - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (2):351-378.
    Finitely algebraizable deductive systems were introduced by Blok and Pigozzi to capture the essential properties of those deductive systems that are very tightly connected to quasivarieties of universal algebras. They include the equivalential logics of Czelakowski. Based on Blok and Pigozzi’s work, Herrmann defined algebraizable deductive systems. These are the equivalential deductive systems that are also truth-equational, in the sense that the truth predicate of the class of their reduced matrix models is explicitly definable by some set of unary equations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Correspondences between Gentzen and Hilbert Systems.J. G. Raftery - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (3):903 - 957.
    Most Gentzen systems arising in logic contain few axiom schemata and many rule schemata. Hilbert systems, on the other hand, usually contain few proper inference rules and possibly many axioms. Because of this, the two notions tend to serve different purposes. It is common for a logic to be specified in the first instance by means of a Gentzen calculus, whereupon a Hilbert-style presentation ‘for’ the logic may be sought—or vice versa. Where this has occurred, the word ‘for’ has taken (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the complexity of the Leibniz hierarchy.Tommaso Moraschini - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (7):805-824.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Categorical Abstract Algebraic Logic: Algebraic Semantics for (documentclass{article}usepackage{amssymb}begin{document}pagestyle{empty}$bf{pi }$end{document})‐Institutions.George Voutsadakis - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (3):177-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Poset of All Logics III: Finitely Presentable Logics.Ramon Jansana & Tommaso Moraschini - 2020 - Studia Logica 109 (3):539-580.
    A logic in a finite language is said to be finitely presentable if it is axiomatized by finitely many finite rules. It is proved that binary non-indexed products of logics that are both finitely presentable and finitely equivalential are essentially finitely presentable. This result does not extend to binary non-indexed products of arbitrary finitely presentable logics, as shown by a counterexample. Finitely presentable logics are then exploited to introduce finitely presentable Leibniz classes, and to draw a parallel between the Leibniz (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Representations of structural closure operators.José Gil-Férez - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (1-2):45-73.
    We continue the work of Blok and Jónsson by developing the theory of structural closure operators and introducing the notion of a representation between them. Similarities and equivalences of Blok-Jónsson turn out to be bijective representations and bijective structural representations, respectively. We obtain a characterization for representations induced by a transformer. In order to obtain a similar characterization for structural representations we introduce the notions of a graduation and a graded variable of an M-set. We show that several deductive systems, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An Algebraic View of Super-Belnap Logics.Hugo Albuquerque, Adam Přenosil & Umberto Rivieccio - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (6):1051-1086.
    The Belnap–Dunn logic is a well-known and well-studied four-valued logic, but until recently little has been known about its extensions, i.e. stronger logics in the same language, called super-Belnap logics here. We give an overview of several results on these logics which have been proved in recent works by Přenosil and Rivieccio. We present Hilbert-style axiomatizations, describe reduced matrix models, and give a description of the lattice of super-Belnap logics and its connections with graph theory. We adopt the point of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)In Memory of Willem Johannes Blok 1947-2003.Joel Berman, Wieslaw Dziobiak, Don Pigozzi & James Raftery - 2006 - Studia Logica 83 (1-3):5-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Willem Blok's Contribution to Abstract Algebraic Logic.Ramon Jansana - 2006 - Studia Logica 83 (1-3):31-48.
    Willem Blok was one of the founders of the field Abstract Algebraic Logic. The paper describes his research in this field.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations