Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mill on liberty and morality

Philosophical Review 81 (2):133-158 (1972)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Mill’s Moral Standard.Ben Eggleston - 2016 - In Christopher Macleod & Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. pp. 358-373.
    A book chapter (about 7,000 words, plus references) on the interpretation of Mill’s criterion of right and wrong, with particular attention to act utilitarianism, rule utilitarianism, and sanction utilitarianism. Along the way, major topics include Mill’s thoughts on liberalism, supererogation, the connection between wrongness and punishment, and breaking rules when doing so will produce more happiness than complying with them will.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral i naše vreme.Jovan Babić - 1998 - Belgrade, Serbia: Službeni glasnik.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mill on Liberty, Speech, and the Free Society.Daniel Jacobson - 2000 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3):276-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • “Harm” and Mill’s Harm Principle.Piers Norris Turner - 2014 - Ethics 124 (2):299-326.
    This article addresses the long-standing problem of how to understand Mill’s famous harm principle in light of his failure to specify what counts as “harm” in On Liberty. I argue that standard accounts restricting “harm” to only certain negative consequences fail to do justice to the text, and that this fact forces us to rethink Mill’s defense of individual liberty. I then offer a new account of that defense in which “harm” is understood in an expansive sense, despite apparent problems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • What is Mill's Principle of Utility?D. G. Brown - 1973 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):1-12.
    In mill the principle of utility does not ascribe rightness or wrongness to anything. It governs not just morality but the whole art of life. It says that happiness is the only thing desirable as an end. But the meaning of this formulation is problematic, Since mill's theory of practical reason conceives this desirability as an end as generating reasons for action for all agents in a way implying impartiality between self and others, Whereas in the ordinary sense it does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mill’s moral theory: Ongoing revisionism.D. G. Brown - 2010 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 9 (1):5-45.
    Revisionist interpretation of Mill needs to be extended to deal with a residue of puzzles about his moral theory and its connection with his theory of liberty. The upshot shows his reinterpretation of his Benthamite tradition as a form of ‘philosophical utilitarianism’; his definition of the art of morality as collective self-defence; his ignoring of maximization in favour of ad hoc dealing in utilities; the central role of his account of the justice of punishment; the marginal role of the internal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • "Otro" liberalismo. Individualismo y colectivismo en la obra de John Stuart Mill.Félix Aguirre - 2017 - Ideas Y Valores 66 (164):229-249.
    El artículo argumenta que, contrario a lo que sostiene el neoliberalismo contem-poráneo, lo individual y lo colectivo no constituyen los extremos de una antítesis ante la que estemos obligados a elegir. Se examina el debate político de la segunda mitad del siglo victoriano sobre la pertinencia y los límites de la intervención esta-tal. Tomando como pretexto la obra de un pensador cuya posición sobre la libertad negativa marcará la historia del liberalismo positivo y del colectivismo, se concluye que la ideología (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mill′s Principle of Liberty.Y. N. Chopra - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (270):417-441.
    Although J. S. Mill′s essay On Liberty was intended by its author to be read as a self-contained work,1 and even though a careful reading would justify seeing it in this way, it has far too often been denied this right even by its defenders. There is a crucial distinction to be made between eliciting some point of substance from a particular work by an author and then turning to the rest of his work to throw further light on it, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Liberty and Compulsory Education.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 15:109-129.
    Although it is primarily concerned with the value of liberty and the justification of compulsory education, what lies behind much of this paper is the question ‘;Why treat children like children?’ The fact is that we do not regard children as having the same rights, privileges and liberties as adults, and children may not be thought of as deserving the same degree of respect or consideration as their seniors. In the past this has led to some horrific states of affairs, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Liberty and Compulsory Education.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 15:109-129.
    Although it is primarily concerned with the value of liberty and the justification of compulsory education, what lies behind much of this paper is the question ‘;Why treat children like children?’ The fact is that we do not regard children as having the same rights, privileges and liberties as adults, and children may not be thought of as deserving the same degree of respect or consideration as their seniors. In the past this has led to some horrific states of affairs, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mill’s Progressive Principles.David O. Brink - 2013 - Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    David O. Brink offers a reconstruction and assessment of John Stuart Mill's contributions to the utilitarian and liberal traditions. Brink defends interpretations of key elements in Mill's moral and political thought, and shows how a perfectionist reading of his conception of happiness has a significant impact on other aspects of his philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Millian Liberalism and Colonial Oppression.D. G. Brown - 1999 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 25 (Supplement):79-97.
    (1999). Millian Liberalism and Colonial Oppression. Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 29, Supplementary Volume 25: Civilization and Oppression, pp. 79-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • J.S. Mill's Puzzling Position on Prostitution and his Harm Principle.Mark Tunick - 2024 - Philosophy 99 (1):1-25.
    J.S. Mill argues against licensing or forced medical examinations of prostitutes even if these would reduce harm, for two reasons: the state should not legitimize immoral conduct; and coercing prostitutes would violate Mill's harm principle as they do not risk causing non-consensual harm to others, their clients do. There is nothing puzzling about Mill opposing coercive restrictions on self-regarding immoral conduct while also opposing state support of that conduct. But why does Mill oppose restrictions on prostitutes’ liberty if those restrictions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mill's Intentions and Motives.Michael Ridge - 2002 - Utilitas 14 (1):54.
    One might have thought that any right-thinking utilitarian would hold that motives and intentions are morally on a par, as either might influence the consequences of one's actions. However, in a neglected passage of Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill claims that the rightness of an action depends 'entirely upon the intention' but does not at all depend upon the motive. In this paper I try to make sense of Mill's initially puzzling remarks about the relative importance of intentions and motives in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The neutrality myth: why international sporting associations and politics cannot be separated.Hans Erik Næss - 2018 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 45 (2):144-160.
    ABSTRACTInternational sporting associations like the International Federation of Football Associations, the International Olympic Committee and Fédération Internationale de l’Automobile have throughout the twentieth century promoted political neutrality as a source of autonomy. With FIFA and the IOC’s official adherence to the United Nations’ human rights conventions in 2017, FIA remains one of the few large ISAs where neutrality is not underpinned by a corrective on human rights. However, this position is in conflict with the ethical obligations FIA contracted when it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On State, Identity and Rights: Putting Identity First.Jovan Babić - 2012 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 25 (2):197-209.
    The paper considers the nature of the state understood as the political unity articulated on the basis of a collective identity which provides the state with its capacity to make decisions. The foremost decision of the state to protect and defend this identity is the source of its authority to enforce laws. Collective identity thus represents an object of special interest, unlike both “political” interests (Millian other-regarding acts) and private interests (Millian self-regarding acts). The validation of laws through this special (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liberty and Harm to Others.David Lyons - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (sup1):1-19.
    J s mill's principle of liberty is often thought to say that the only good reason for interfering with a person's conduct is that it is harmful to others. An alternative interpretation is defended: that the only good reason for interfering is to prevent harm to others. Harm-Prevention is the aim, But the latter principle allows that conduct affected not be harmful; interference must be calculated to prevent harm to others, Perhaps indirectly. This accords with mill's official statement of his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Good and the Right.L. W. Sumner - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 5:99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rights and Utilitarianism.Jan Narveson - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (sup1):137-160.
    Few questions about utilitarianism have been more vexed than that of its relation to rights. It is commonplace to hold that there are nonutilitarian rights, rights not founded on considerations of utility. And it is even thought that the very notion of rights is inherently incapable of being significantly employed within the utilitarian framework. In the present paper, I wish to consider both of these matters. I propose to give reasons—mostly not really new—for rejecting the stronger, conceptual claim; and on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How to Preach.Michael McDermott - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (4):633 - 652.
    That's what I reckon morality is all about — how to preach, not how to act. My aim is not to answer this question of how to preach. I want to defend the claim that it is the, or at least a, central problem of ethics: that it is in fact the problem of what moral principles to accept.My argument consists of an account of what is involved in accepting a moral principle. By a moral principle I mean a kind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Liberty and Harm to Others.David Lyons - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 5:1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Indirect Utility and Fundamental Rights.John Gray - 1984 - Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (2):73.
    A TRADITIONAL VIEW OF UTILITY AND RIGHTS According to a conventional view, no project could be more hopelessly misconceived than the enterprise of attempting a utilitarian derivation of fundamental rights. We are all familiar – too familiar, perhaps – with the arguments that support this conventional view, but let us review them anyway. We may begin by recalling that, whereas the defining value of utilitarianism – pleasure, happiness or welfare – contains no mention of the dignity or autonomy of human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Was Mill a Utilitarian?Christopher Miles Coope - 1998 - Utilitas 10 (1):33.
    Mill was receptive to all sorts of ideas, both plausible and implausible, which did not fit well with utilitarianism. He was, for example, inclined to think of equality, not just pleasure, as. He was able to think of himself as a utilitarian only by grossly expanding that notion to cover any doctrine which did not entirely rely, without the possibility of further explanation, on or God's commands. It is even doubtful whether he was a consequentialist in any sense. Mill's account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mill on Liberty of Self-Development.Wendy Donner - 1987 - Dialogue 26 (2):227.
    John Stuart Mill's commitment to liberty and individual development is one of the most exoteric themes of his moral and political philosophy. But the linkages between this commitment to liberty and development and Mill's conception of utility and principles of the good are not as commonly recognized. As part of a more general transformation of his utilitarianism, Mill repudiated Bentham's principles of the good and instead adopted a more sophisticated form of hedonism. While Bentham admits only the total quantity of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mill's Criterion of Wrong Conduct.D. G. Brown - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (1):27-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • John Stuart Mill on Justice and Fairness.F. R. Berger - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 5:115-136.
    The main difficulty utilitarians have faced is the problem of reconciling the dictates of utility with what seem clearly to be moral duties, but based on considerations of Justice. John Stuart Mill addressed this problem in his essay,Utilitarianism,and the result has not served to silence the critics of utilitarianism on this score. In part, this is due to the fact that Mill's position in the chapter on Justice is not entirely clear, nor is it entirely convincing where it is clear. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Stuart Mill on Justice and Fairness.F. R. Berger - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (sup1):115-136.
    The main difficulty utilitarians have faced is the problem of reconciling the dictates of utility with what seem clearly to be moral duties, but based on considerations of Justice. John Stuart Mill addressed this problem in his essay,Utilitarianism,and the result has not served to silence the critics of utilitarianism on this score. In part, this is due to the fact that Mill's position in the chapter on Justice is not entirely clear, nor is it entirely convincing where it is clear. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Another” liberalism. Individualism and collectivism in the work of John Stuart Mill.Félix Aguirre - 2017 - Ideas Y Valores 66 (164):229-249.
    RESUMEN El artículo argumenta que, contrario a lo que sostiene el neoliberalismo contemporáneo, lo individual y lo colectivo no constituyen los extremos de una antítesis ante la que estemos obligados a elegir. Se examina el debate político de la segunda mitad del siglo victoriano sobre la pertinencia y los límites de la intervención estatal. Tomando como pretexto la obra de un pensador cuya posición sobre la libertad negativa marcará la historia del liberalismo positivo y del colectivismo, se concluye que la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark