Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The land ethic and Callicott's ethical system (1980-2001): An overview and critique.Y. S. Lo - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):331 – 358.
    This article analyzes the evolution of the land ethic re-presented by J. Baird Callicott over the last two decades under pressure from the charge of misanthropy and ecofascism. It also traces the development of Callicott?s own ethical system, and examines its most current phase both in itself and in relation to his other theoretical commitments, including his particular version of moral monism, and his communitarian critique of egalitarianism. It concludes that Callicott?s communitarianism is by itself insufficient to fund an adequate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What's In a Name? Pragmatism, Essentialism, and Environmental Ethics.Mark A. Michael - 2003 - Environmental Values 12 (3):361-379.
    Essentialists like J. Baird Callicott have argued that one cannot have an environmental ethic unless one adopts the nonanthropocentric principle, which holds that things other than humans can be morally considerable in their own right, typically because they are thought to be intrinsically valuable. Pragmatists like Bryan Norton reject this; they claim that environmental ethics has no core or essence, and hence that the nonanthropocentric principle is not essential to an environmental ethic. Norton advances as an alternative the Convergence Hypothesis, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Environmental ethics beyond principle? The case for a pragmatic contextualism.Ben A. Minteer, Elizabeth A. Corley & Robert E. Manning - 2004 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 17 (2):131-156.
    Many nonanthropocentric environmental ethicists subscribe to a ``principle-ist'''' approach to moral argument, whereby specific natural resource and environmental policy judgments are deduced from the prior articulation of a general moral principle. More often than not, this principle is one requiring the promotion of the intrinsic value of nonhuman nature. Yet there are several problems with this method of moral reasoning, including the short-circuiting of reflective inquiry and the disregard of the complex nature of specific environmental problems and policy arguments. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Pragmatism, Pluralism, Empiricism and Relational Values.Piers H. G. Stephens - 2021 - Environmental Values 30 (6):661-668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Asian traditions of knowledge: The disputed questions of science, nature and ecology.A. Brennan - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):567-581.
    The search for 'ecological insights' in venerable Asian traditions of thought prompts questions about how such traditions understood humans in relation to nature. Answers which focus on philosophical and religious ideas may overlook culturally important understandings of people and places articulated within scientific and medical thinking. The paper tentatively explores the prospects for gleaning a form of ethics of place from the study of traditional Hindu and Chinese medical sources. Although there are serious problems with the idea that any unadulterated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The natural environment as a salient stakeholder: Non-anthropocentrism, ecosystem stability and the financial markets.Simon D. Norton - 2007 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 16 (4):387–402.
    The current debate as to whether the natural environment should be accorded stakeholder status involves an assumption that it is in some way ‘different’ from other stakeholders, requiring favourable discriminatory treatment. Essentially it is regarded as passive, requiring regulatory agencies to represent its interests or the wider public to demand its protection on the occasion of, for example, oil spills that leave wildlife in a visibly distressed state. But the natural environment does not have ‘consciousness’ as do traditional classes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The natural environment as a salient stakeholder: non-anthropocentrism, ecosystem stability and the financial markets.Simon D. Norton - 2007 - Business Ethics: A European Review 16 (4):387-402.
    The current debate as to whether the natural environment should be accorded stakeholder status involves an assumption that it is in some way ‘different’ from other stakeholders, requiring favourable discriminatory treatment. Essentially it is regarded as passive, requiring regulatory agencies to represent its interests or the wider public to demand its protection on the occasion of, for example, oil spills that leave wildlife in a visibly distressed state. But the natural environment does not have ‘consciousness’ as do traditional classes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Asian traditions of knowledge: the disputed questions of science, nature and ecology.Andrew Brennan - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):567-581.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation