Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Philosophy of Rhetoric

Printed by George Ramsay & Co. For William Creech, Edinburgh; and T. Cadell and W. Davies, London (2009)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Common Sense Rhetorical Theory, Pluralism, and Protestant Natural Law.Rosaleen Keefe - 2013 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 11 (2):213-228.
    This paper offers re-assessment of Scottish Common Sense rhetoric and its relationship to pluralist practice and philosophical method. It argues that the rhetorical texts of George Campbell, Hugh Blair, and Alexander Bain can be read as a practical application of Scottish Common Sense philosophy. This offers a novel means of examining the relationship that Scottish rhetoric has to the philosophy of David Hume and also its own innovative philosophy of language. Finally, I argue that Scottish rhetoric makes a unique contribution (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ambiguous Weighting and Nonsensical Sense: The Problems of “Balance” and “Common Sense” as Commonplace Concepts and Decision-making Heuristics in Environmental Rhetoric.Derek G. Ross - 2012 - Social Epistemology 26 (1):115-144.
    Balance and common sense are commonplace concepts used to bring an audience to a place of shared understanding. These commonplaces also function as decision-making heuristics. I argue in this paper that the commonplaces ?balance? and ?common sense? are problematic because they suggest decision-making strategies that strip associated information of complexity and value. Through an examination of theory and responses to interviews conducted in relation to an ongoing project on environmental rhetoric, I problematize these concepts and consider how awareness of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conviction, Persuasion, and Argumentation: Untangling the Ends and Means of Influence. [REVIEW]Daniel J. O’Keefe - 2012 - Argumentation 26 (1):19-32.
    This essay offers a start on sorting out the relationships of argumentation and persuasion by identifying two systematic ways in which definitions of argumentation differ, namely, their descriptions of the ends and of the means involved in argumentative discourse. Against that backdrop, the traditional “conviction-persuasion” distinction is reassessed. The essay argues that the traditional distinction correctly recognizes the difference between the end of influencing attitudes and that of influencing behavior—but that it misanalyzes the means of achieving the latter (by focusing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Alexander Broadie (ed.), Thomas Reid on logic, rhetoric and the fine arts edinburgh university press, edinburgh (2005), 350 pp. isbn 0-7486-1684-5 (hardback). [REVIEW]Marion Ledwig - 2006 - Theoria 72 (3):248-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Hume on Liberty and Necessity.Godfrey Vesey - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20:111-127.
    David Hume (1711–1776) described the question of liberty and necessity as ‘the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science’ (Hume [1748] 1975, p. 95). He was right about it being contentious. Whether it is metaphysical is another matter. I think that what is genuinely metaphysical is an assumption that Hume, and a good many other philosophers, make in their treatment of the question. The assumption is about language and reality. I call it ‘the conformity assumption’. But more about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethics, Rhetoric, and Expectations: Responsibilities and Obligations of Health Care Systems.Thomas Foreman - 2014 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 11 (3):295-299.
    Health care organization foundations and other fund-raising departments often function at an arm’s length from the system at large. As such, operations related to their mandate to raise funds and market the organization do not receive the same level of ethical scrutiny brought to bear on other arms within the organization. An area that could benefit from a more focused ethics lens is the use of language and rhetoric employed in order to raise funds and market the organization. Such departments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The medium of signs: nominalism, language and the philosophy of mind in the early thought of Dugald Stewart.M. D. Eddy - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (3):373-393.
    In 1792 Dugald Stewart published Elements of the philosophy of the human mind. In its section on abstraction he declared himself to be a nominalist. Although a few scholars have made brief reference to this position, no sustained attention has been given to the central role that it played within Stewart’s early philosophy of mind. It is therefore the purpose of this essay to unpack Stewart’s nominalism and the intellectual context that fostered it. In the first three sections I aver (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reason as a Nexus of Natural Law and Rhetoric.Jeffrey J. Maciejewski - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 59 (3):247-257.
    . Although the pages of Journal of Business Ethics have hosted an ongoing dialogue on the ethics of rhetoric and persuasion, the debates have been unable to account for the underlying morality of the human propensity to engage in rhetorical discourse as a part of living in society. In this paper, I offer natural-law ethical theory as a moral paradigm in which to examine rhetoric. In this context, I assert that rhetoric services reason, which in turn services our dispositions or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Structural Idealism: A Theory of Social and Historical Explanation.Douglas Mann - 2006 - Wilfrid Laurier Univ. Press.
    Do we determine our actions, or are our actions ruled by the structure of our society? Does our culture create us, or do we create our culture? Within history and social theory there is a fundamental division of opinion between those who explain human action by considering the intentions, reasons and motives of individuals and those who use broader social structures. Structural Idealism presents a theory of social and historical explanation which argues that “idealists” such as Hegel, who champion human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark