Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Althusser/Bachelard : Une coupure et ses enjeux.Andrea Cavazzini - 2015 - Revue de Synthèse 136 (1-2):117-134.
    Louis Althusser s'est réclamé de Bachelard et de l'épistémologie historique française pour fonder sa propre entreprise de reconstruction du marxisme. Pourtant, la nature et le fonctionnement réels de ces emprunts sont loin d'être univoques. Le lien entre Bachelard et Althusser a été souvent réduit à une série de formules figées qui ont fini par cacher les usages de l'épistémologie chez Althusser et la pensée des sciences qu'ils impliquent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From the historical a priori to the dispositif: Foucault, the phenomenological legacy, and the problem of transcendental genesis.Kevin Thompson - 2016 - Continental Philosophy Review 49 (1):41-54.
    What philosophical motivations lay behind the emergence of the genealogical method in Foucault’s thought? Pace traditional interpretations, I argue that genealogy is best construed as a supplementary addition to the archaeological mode of investigation. It addresses an issue that arose within the problematic to which the archaeological method responds, but which that method was not designed to solve: the problem of “transcendental genesis” as this issue was defined within the unique parameters set forth by the French phenomenological tradition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cerebral Drawings between Art and Science: On Gilles Deleuze’s Philosophy of Concepts.Henning Schmidgen - 2015 - Theory, Culture and Society 32 (7-8):123-149.
    In What Is Philosophy?, Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari distinguish the functions of philosophy, art and science. According to this distinction, the primary purpose of philosophy is to invent concepts, the purpose of art to bring forth percepts, or sensorial aggregates, and that of science to delineate functions. This article aims to show that these distinctions are not as clear-cut as they appear. Using Deleuze and Guattari’s proposition that ‘philosophy is the art of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts’ as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hermann Weyl motivations philosophiques d'un choixMaverik.Demetrio Ria - 2005 - Revue de Synthèse 126 (2):463-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deleuze Challenges Kolmogorov on a Calculus of Problems.Jean-Claude Dumoncel - 2013 - Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 7 (2):169-193.
    In 1932 Kolmogorov created a calculus of problems. This calculus became known to Deleuze through a 1945 paper by Paulette Destouches-Février. In it, he ultimately recognised a deepening of mathematical intuitionism. However, from the beginning, he proceeded to show its limits through a return to the Leibnizian project of Calculemus taken in its metaphysical stance. In the carrying out of this project, which is illustrated through a paradigm borrowed from Spinoza, the formal parallelism between problems, Leibnizian themes and Peircean rhemes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strenge Beweise und das Verbot der metábasis eis állo génos : Eine Untersuchung zu Bernard Bolzanos Beyträgen zu einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (1):1 - 31.
    In his booklet "Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics" of 1810 Bernard Bolzano made his first serious attempt to explain the notion of a rigorous proof. Although the system of logic he employed at that stage is in various respects far below the level of the achievements in his later Wissenschaftslehre, there is a striking continuity between his earlier and later work as regards the methodological constraints on rigorous proofs. This paper tries to give a perspicuous and critical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strenge Beweise und das Verbot der metábasis eis állo génos : Eine Untersuchung zu Bernard Bolzanos Beyträgen zu einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (1):1-31.
    In his booklet ‘Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics’ of 1810 Bernard Bolzano made his first serious attempt to explain the notion of a rigorous proof. Although the system of logic he employed at that stage is in various respects far below the level of the achievements in his later Wissenschaftslehre, there is a striking continuity between his earlier and later work as regards the methodological constraints on rigorous proofs. This paper tries to give a perspicuous and critical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cavaillès, mathematical problems and questions.Pierre Cassou-Noguès - 2018 - Angelaki 23 (2):64-78.
    This paper concerns the role of mathematical problems in the epistemology of Jean Cavaillès. Most occurrences of the term “problem” in his texts refer to mathematical problems, in the sense in which mathematicians themselves use the term: for an unsolved question which they hope to solve. Mathematical problems appear as breaking points in the succession of mathematical theories, both giving a continuity to the history of mathematics and illuminating the way in which the history of mathematics breaks up into successive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is Modern in the Crisis of European Sciences?Gabriele Baratelli - 2022 - Husserl Studies 38 (3):293-311.
    Although the notion of the crisis of European sciences has a general meaning, Husserl mainly focuses on this phenomenon in relation to the modern establishment of a mathematical natural science. However, he does not provide a definitive clarification of how its new method is specifically involved in bringing about such a crisis. Without trying to offer a faithful exegetical contribution, this paper further elaborates on Husserl’s analyses in the Krisis to give a possible answer to this question. After defining the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Albert Lautman et le souci brisé du mouvement.Charles Alunni - 2005 - Revue de Synthèse 126 (2):283-301.
    Nous posons l'oeuvre d'Albert Lautman comme une sorte d'opérateur de brisure de symétrie dans le cadre de l'opposition traditionnelle de la philosophie spéculative et des sciences physico-mathématiques. L'enjeu pour la philosophie en est, à de très rares exceptions près, encore très mal perçu. Sur ce plan, nous reprenons la question du « platonisme » supposé de Lautman, et nous le confrontons à sa lecture fondamentale de Martin Heidegger. Les conséquences de cette inscription dans le sillon heideggérien sont fondamentales pour une (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Signs, figures and time: Cavaillès on “intuition” in mathematics.Pierre Cassou-noguès - 2010 - Theoria 21 (1):89-104.
    This paper is concerned with Cavaillès’ account of “intuition” in mathematics. Cavaillès starts from Kant’s theory of constructions in intuition and then relies on various remarks by Hilbert to apply it to modern mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark