Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Clendinnen and salmon on induction as the non-arbitrary method.A. A. Derksen - 1986 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1):72 – 84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inference, practice and theory.F. John Clendinnen - 1977 - Synthese 34 (1):89 - 132.
    Reichenbach held that all scientific inference reduces, via probability calculus, to induction, and he held that induction can be justified. He sees scientific knowledge in a practical context and insists that any rational assessment of actions requires a justification of induction. Gaps remain in his justifying argument; for we can not hope to prove that induction will succeed if success is possible. However, there are good prospects for completing a justification of essentially the kind he sought by showing that while (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A response to Jackson.F. John Clendinnen - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (3):444-448.
    Frank Jackson's criticisms have helped me recognize some of the weaknesses in my proposed vindication of induction. The core of the argument I offered was that induction is the only method of predicting which is based in a nonarbitrary way on the facts. I still believe that this is so and that because of this property induction is the only reasonable way of predicting. However I now recognize defects in the argument by which I attempted to establish that the uniqueness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Does Meta-induction Justify Induction: Or Maybe Something Else?J. Brian Pitts - 2023 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 54 (3):393-419.
    According to the Feigl–Reichenbach–Salmon–Schurz pragmatic justification of induction, no predictive method is guaranteed or even likely to work for predicting the future; but if anything will work, induction will work—at least when induction is employed at the meta-level of predictive methods in light of their track records. One entertains a priori all manner of esoteric prediction methods, and is said to arrive a posteriori at the conclusion, based on the actual past, that object-level induction is optimal. Schurz’s refinements largely solve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Clendinnen, Jackson, and induction.Gary Jones - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (3):466-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reply to a response.Frank Jackson - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (3):449-451.
    While disagreeing with some of the detail of my argument in [2] F. John Clendinnen accepts its conclusion, namely, that the vindication he proposed in [1] fails. I will thus confine myself to saying, very briefly, why I think the new vindication of induction that he sketches in [3] also fails.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A reply to "induction and objectivity".Frank Jackson - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (3):440-443.
    In “Induction and Objectivity” [1], F. John Clendinnen puts forwards a vindication of induction. I wish to argue that the vindication fails. As Clendinnen's argument is complex and presents certain difficulties it is necessary and only fair to quote his summary of it.“I shall attempt to vindicate induction by showing that it is the only possible way of predicting that is objective, and further that, while objectivity is not a necessary condition for success in predicting, objective methods are the only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation