Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Linearity and Reflexivity in the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge.Leo Corry - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (2):409-440.
    The ArgumentRecent studies in the philosophy of mathematics have increasingly stressed the social and historical dimensions of mathematical practice. Although this new emphasis has fathered interesting new perspectives, it has also blurred the distinction between mathematics and other scientific fields. This distinction can be clarified by examining the special interaction of thebodyandimagesof mathematics.Mathematics has an objective, ever-expanding hard core, the growth of which is conditioned by socially and historically determined images of mathematics. Mathematics also has reflexive capacities unlike those of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Leibniz and Russell on Existence and Quantification Theory.Jeffrey Skosnik - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4):681 - 720.
    Never shall this be proved, that things that are not are. ParmenidesTo say that something does not exist, or that there is something which is not, is clearly a contradiction in terms; hence “ ” must be true. Moreover, we should certainly expect leave to put any primitive name of our language for the “x” of any matrix “ … x … ”, and to infer the resulting singular statement from “ ”; it is difficult to contemplate any alternative logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Frege's Approach to the Foundations of Analysis (1874–1903).Matthias Schirn - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (3):266-292.
    The concept of quantity (Größe) plays a key role in Frege's theory of real numbers. Typically enough, he refers to this theory as ?theory of quantity? (?Größenlehre?) in the second volume of his opus magnum Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Frege 1903). In this essay, I deal, in a critical way, with Frege's treatment of the concept of quantity and his approach to analysis from the beginning of his academic career until Frege 1903. I begin with a few introductory remarks. In Section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logic and Divine Simplicity.Anders Kraal - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (4):282-294.
    The paper surveys two contrasting views of first‐order analyses of classical theistic doctrines about the existence and nature of God. On the first view, first‐order logic provides methods for the adequate analysis of these doctrines, for example by construing ‘God’ as a singular term or as a monadic predicate, or by taking it to be a definite description. On the second view, such analyses are conceptually inadequate, at least when the doctrines in question are viewed against the background of classical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From the History of Leśniewski’s Mereology.Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2024 - Studia Humana 13 (1):5-16.
    In this paper, we want to present the genesis of Stanisław Leśniewski’s mereology. Although ‘mereology’ comes from theword ‘part’, mereology arose as a theory of collective classes. That is why we present the differences between the concepts of being a distributive class and being a collective class. Next, we present Leśniewski’s original mereology from 1927, but with a modern approach. Leśniewski was inspired to create his concept of classes and their elements by Russell’s antinomy. To face it, Leśniewski had to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the failure of mathematics' philosophy: Review of P. Maddy, Realism in Mathematics; and C. Chihara, Constructibility and Mathematical Existence.David Charles McCarty - 1993 - Synthese 96 (2):255-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Gödel’s Natural Deduction.Kosta Došen & Miloš Adžić - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (2):397-415.
    This is a companion to a paper by the authors entitled “Gödel on deduction”, which examined the links between some philosophical views ascribed to Gödel and general proof theory. When writing that other paper, the authors were not acquainted with a system of natural deduction that Gödel presented with the help of Gentzen’s sequents, which amounts to Jaśkowski’s natural deduction system of 1934, and which may be found in Gödel’s unpublished notes for the elementary logic course he gave in 1939 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tropes, Particularity, and Space-Time.Vassilios Livanios - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (2):357-368.
    Several difficulties, concerning the individuation and the variation of tropes, beset the initial classic version of trope theory. K. Campbell (Abstract particulars, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1990) presented a modified version that aims to avoid those difficulties. Unfortunately, the revised theory cannot make the case that one of the fundamental tropes, space-time, is a genuine particular.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a logic of experience.Zane Parks - 1972 - Philosophia 2 (3):183-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Frege on Identity and Identity Statements: 1884/1903.Matthias Schirn - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-22.
    In this essay, I first solve solve a conundrum and then deal with criteria of identity, Leibniz's definition of identity and Frege's adoption of it in his (failed) attempt to define the cardinality operator contextually in terms of Hume's Principle in Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. I argue that Frege could have omitted the intermediate step of tentatively defining the cardinality operator in the context of an equation of the form ‘NxF(x) = NxG(x)'. Frege considers Leibniz's definition of identity to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Saul A. Kripke. Semantical analysis of modal logic I. Normal modal propositional calculi. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 9 , pp. 67–96. [REVIEW]David Kaplan - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):120-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • How Do We Learn from Argument?: Toward an Account of the Logic of Problems.Terry M. Goode & John R. Wettersten - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (4):673-689.
    From the pre-Socratics to the present, one primary aim of philosophy has been to learn from arguments. Philosophers have debated whether we could indeed do this, but they have by and large agreed on how we would use arguments if learning from argument was at all possible. They have agreed that we could learn from arguments either by starting with true premises and validly deducing further statements which must also be true and therefore constitute new knowledge, or that we could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Emergence of Logical Formalization in the Philosophy of Religion: Genesis, Crisis, and Rehabilitation.Anders Kraal - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (4):351 - 366.
    The paper offers a historical survey of the emergence of logical formalization in twentieth-century analytically oriented philosophy of religion. This development is taken to have passed through three main ?stages?: a pioneering stage in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (led by Frege and Russell), a stage of crisis in the 1920s and early 1930s (occasioned by Wittgenstein, logical positivists such as Carnap, and neo-Thomists such as Maritain), and a stage of rehabilitation in the 1930s, 1940s, and 1950s (led (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • If Logic, Definitions and the Vicious Circle Principle.Jaakko Hintikka - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (2):505-517.
    In a definition (∀ x )(( x є r )↔D[ x ]) of the set r, the definiens D[ x ] must not depend on the definiendum r . This implies that all quantifiers in D[ x ] are independent of r and of (∀ x ). This cannot be implemented in the traditional first-order logic, but can be expressed in IF logic. Violations of such independence requirements are what created the typical paradoxes of set theory. Poincaré’s Vicious Circle Principle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Russell on constructions and fictions.R. M. Sainsbury - 1980 - Theoria 46 (1):19-36.
    Russell says that logical constructions are fictions. Does this show that he took them not to be real things?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A leśniewskian re-examination of Goodman's nominalistic rejection of classes.Judith M. Prakel - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):87-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bertrand Russell's theory of judgment.Russell Wahl - 1986 - Synthese 68 (3):383 - 407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Language and the Logic of Subjectivity: Whitehead and Burke in Crisis.Joshua DiCaglio - 2017 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 50 (1):96-118.
    Bruno Latour, the increasingly popular French philosopher and foundational thinker for science studies, once wrote: “I know neither who I am nor what I want, but others say they know on my behalf, others who will define me, link me up, make me speak, interpret what I say, and enroll me”. This invocation of an “other” as a self-definition is no longer surprising nor radical but has long been a common answer to Plato’s famous and persistent insistence that we must, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Russell as a platonic dialogue: The matter of denoting.J. Alberto Coffa - 1980 - Synthese 45 (1):43-70.
    At first russell thought (p) that whatever a proposition is about must be a constituent of it. Then, Around 1900, He discovered denoting concepts and realized that a proposition could be about something and have only its denoting concept as constituent. However, A number of remarks that he made through the years can only be understood as inspired by (p). In particular, The arguments offered in "on denoting" against the doctrine of denotation of "principles" are grounded on (p).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Argument and belief: Where we stand in the Keynesian tradition. [REVIEW]R. P. Loui - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (4):357-365.
    There is the idea that rational belief for a single individual can be constructed via a process of unilateral argument. To preempt antipathy between the AI communities that can claim the idea that rational belief can be so constructed, we trace the idea to the beginning of this century, to Keynes' dispute with Russell over logic and probability. We review how Keynesian ideas were revived in AI's work on non-monotonic reasoning and parallel developments in philosophical logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Schönfinkel-type Operators for Classical Logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2010 - Studia Logica 95 (3):355-378.
    We briefly overview some of the historical landmarks on the path leading to the reduction of the number of logical connectives in classical logic. Relying on the duality inherent in Boolean algebras, we introduce a new operator ( Nallor ) that is the dual of Schönfinkel’s operator. We outline the proof that this operator by itself is sufficient to define all the connectives and operators of classical first-order logic ( Fol ). Having scrutinized the proof, we pinpoint the theorems of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Indefinability of “One”.Laurence Goldstein - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (1):29-42.
    Logicism is one of the great reductionist projects. Numbers and the relationships in which they stand may seem to possess suspect ontological credentials – to be entia non grata – and, further, to be beyond the reach of knowledge. In seeking to reduce mathematics to a small set of principles that form the logical basis of all reasoning, logicism holds out the prospect of ontological economy and epistemological security. This paper attempts to show that a fundamental logicist project, that of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spinozist monism.Peter Loptson - 1988 - Philosophia 18 (1):19-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Designing post-industrial organizations for ecological sustainability.Ronald Purser - 1996 - World Futures 46 (4):203-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logicism as Making Arithmetic Explicit.Vojtěch Kolman - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (3):487-503.
    This paper aims to shed light on the broader significance of Frege’s logicism against the background of discussing and comparing Wittgenstein’s ‘showing/saying’-distinction with Brandom’s idiom of logic as the enterprise of making the implicit rules of our linguistic practices explicit. The main thesis of this paper is that the problem of Frege’s logicism lies deeper than in its inconsistency : it lies in the basic idea that in arithmetic one can, and should, express everything that is implicitly presupposed so that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Une grammaire de l'incomplétude référentielle: la logique intensionnelle des Principia Mathematica.Jocelyne Couture - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (1):69-90.
    Cet article s'ajoute à la liste déjà longue de ceux qui traitent des rapports entre la théorie russellienne des descriptions définies et la théorie ramifiée des types. Seule la prétention d'aborder cette question dans une perspective nouvelle justifie ici sa présence: d'une part, la théorie des descriptions définies sera resituée dans le contexte initial et souvent méconnu de la théorie des expressions dénotantes et d'autre part, c'est à la logique intensionnelle de Russell, objet d'une méconnaissance au moins égale, que nous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thesis: Religion and the human situation.Bowman Clarke - 1970 - World Futures 8 (4):2-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark