Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. La genèse de la méthode cartésienne : la mathesis universalis et la rédaction de la quatrième des Règles pour la direction de l’esprit.Érico Andrade M. de Oliveira - 2010 - Dialogue 49 (2):173-198.
    ABSTRACT : On many accounts, Rule IV appears to be composed of two distinct texts, and this should be justified by the difference between the mathesis universalis and the Cartesian method. This article runs counter to the usual interpretation by showing that the discussion on mathematics in Rule IV has enabled the introduction of method constraining scientific research to operate on grounds of order and measurement. The mathesis universalis is not so much a science of higher mathematics as a universal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction: The Idiosyncratic Nature of Renaissance Mathematics.Paolo Rossini - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (3):353-357.
    Ever since its foundation in 1540, the Society of Jesus had had one mission—to restore order where Luther, Calvin and the other instigators of the Reformation had brought chaos. To stop the hemorrhage of believers, the Jesuits needed to form a united front. No signs of internal disagreement could to be shown to the outside world, lest the congregation lose its credibility. But in 1570s two prominent Jesuits, Cristophorus Clavius and Benito Perera, had engaged in a bitter controversy. The issue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • François Viète’s revolution in algebra.Jeffrey A. Oaks - 2018 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 (3):245-302.
    Françios Viète was a geometer in search of better techniques for astronomical calculation. Through his theorem on angular sections he found a use for higher-dimensional geometric magnitudes which allowed him to create an algebra for geometry. We show that unlike traditional numerical algebra, the knowns and unknowns in Viète’s logistice speciosa are the relative sizes of non-arithmetized magnitudes in which the “calculations” must respect dimension. Along with this foundational shift Viète adopted a radically new notation based in Greek geometric equalities. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Can a machine think ? Automation beyond simulation.M. Beatrice Fazi - 2019 - AI and Society 34 (4):813-824.
    This article will rework the classical question ‘Can a machine think?’ into a more specific problem: ‘Can a machine think anything new?’ It will consider traditional computational tasks such as prediction and decision-making, so as to investigate whether the instrumentality of these operations can be understood in terms of the creation of novel thought. By addressing philosophical and technoscientific attempts to mechanise thought on the one hand, and the philosophical and cultural critique of these attempts on the other, I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Can a machine think ? Automation beyond simulation.M. Beatrice Fazi - 2019 - AI and Society 34 (4):813-824.
    This article will rework the classical question ‘Can a machine think?’ into a more specific problem: ‘Can a machine think anything new?’ It will consider traditional computational tasks such as prediction and decision-making, so as to investigate whether the instrumentality of these operations can be understood in terms of the creation of novel thought. By addressing philosophical and technoscientific attempts to mechanise thought on the one hand, and the philosophical and cultural critique of these attempts on the other, I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ideación, ocultación e interpretación del relato onírico cartesiano.Susana Gómez López - 2022 - Pensamiento 78 (300 Extra):1541-1566.
    Los famosos sueños de Descartes han constituido siempre para la historia de la filosofía un incómodo problema, pues dejaban la puerta abierta a la posibilidad de que el origen de la moderna racionalidad hubiese nacido de lo irracional. Superar este problema no fue fácil para el propio Descartes pasados los años ni lo ha sido para quienes desde entonces han mantenido que sus ideas marcaron el origen de una etapa de la filosofía y la ciencia caracterizada por el rechazo de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Geometry and the Gods: Theurgy_ in Proclus’s _Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements.Robert Goulding - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (3):358-406.
    The gods that guard the poles have been assigned the function of assembling the separate and unifying the manifold members of the whole, while those appointed to the axes keep the circuits in everlasting revolution around and around. And if I may add my own conceit, the centers and poles of all the spheres symbolize the wry-necked gods by imitating the mysterious union and synthesis which they effect; the axes represent the connectors of all the cosmic orders … and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and Salvation in Jesuit Culture.Rivka Feldhay - 1987 - Science in Context 1 (2):195-213.
    The ArgumentIn this paper, I argue that the most significant contribution of the Jesuits to early modern science consists in the introduction of a new “image of knowledge.”In contradistinction to traditional Scholasticism, this image of knowledge allows for the possibility of a science of hypothetical entities.This problem became crucial in two specific areas. In astronomy, knowledge of mathematical entities of unclear ontological status was nevertheless proclaimed certain. In theology, God's knowledge of the future acts of man, logically considered as future (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logic of imagination. Echoes of Cartesian epistemology in contemporary philosophy of mathematics and beyond.David Rabouin - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):4751-4783.
    Descartes’ Rules for the direction of the mind presents us with a theory of knowledge in which imagination, considered as an “aid” for the intellect, plays a key role. This function of schematization, which strongly resembles key features of Proclus’ philosophy of mathematics, is in full accordance with Descartes’ mathematical practice in later works such as La Géométrie from 1637. Although due to its reliance on a form of geometric intuition, it may sound obsolete, I would like to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Between Viète and Descartes: Adriaan van Roomen and the Mathesis Universalis.Paul Bockstaele - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (4):433-470.
    Adriaan van Roomen published an outline of what he called a Mathesis Universalis in 1597. This earned him a well-deserved place in the history of early modern ideas about a universal mathematics which was intended to encompass both geometry and arithmetic and to provide general rules valid for operations involving numbers, geometrical magnitudes, and all other quantities amenable to measurement and calculation. ‘Mathesis Universalis’ (MU) became the most common (though not the only) term for mathematical theories developed with that aim. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations