Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A combinatory account of internal structure.Barry Jay & Thomas Given-Wilson - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (3):807 - 826.
    Traditional combinatory logic uses combinators S and K to represent all Turing-computable functions on natural numbers, but there are Turing-computable functions on the combinators themselves that cannot be so represented, because they access internal structure in ways that S and K cannot. Much of this expressive power is captured by adding a factorisation combinator F. The resulting SF-calculus is structure complete, in that it supports all pattern-matching functions whose patterns are in normal form, including a function that decides structural equality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Logique hégélienne et formalisation.Yvon Gauthier - 1967 - Dialogue 6 (2):151-165.
    Le problème de la formalisation de la logique hégélienne a fait l'objet récemment d'études d'inspiration et d'importance diverses. II y a d'abord le travail d'envergure de Gotthard Guenther sur le projet d'une logique non-aristotélicienne, le long article de Michael Kosok et la note de F. G. Asenjo.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Upper Bounds for Standardizations and an Application.Hongwei Xi - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1):291-303.
    We present a new proof for the standardization theorem in $\lambda$-calculus, which is largely built upon a structural induction on $\lambda$-terms. We then extract some bounds for the number of $\beta$-reduction steps in the standard $\beta$-reduction sequence obtained from transforming a given $\beta$-reduction sequence, sharpening the standardization theorem. As an application, we establish a super exponential bound for the lengths of $\beta$-reduction sequences from any given simply typed $\lambda$-terms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Completeness of transfinite evaluation in an extension of the lambda calculus.Luis E. Sanchis - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):243-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some results on combinators in the system TRC.Thomas Jech - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1811-1819.
    We investigate the system TRC of untyped illative combinatory logic that is equiconsistent with New Foundations. We prove that various unstratified combinators do not exist in TRC.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Principal type-schemes and condensed detachment.J. Roger Hindley & David Meredith - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):90-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Intuition, Iteration, Induction.Mark van Atten - 2024 - Philosophia Mathematica 32 (1):34-81.
    Brouwer’s view on induction has relatively recently been characterised as one on which it is not only intuitive (as expected) but functional, by van Dalen. He claims that Brouwer’s ‘Ur-intuition’ also yields the recursor. Appealing to Husserl’s phenomenology, I offer an analysis of Brouwer’s view that supports this characterisation and claim, even if assigning the primary role to the iterator instead. Contrasts are drawn to accounts of induction by Poincaré, Heyting, and Kreisel. On the phenomenological side, the analysis provides an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Propositional Forms of Judgemental Interpretations.Tao Xue, Zhaohui Luo & Stergios Chatzikyriakidis - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (4):733-758.
    In formal semantics based on modern type theories, some sentences may be interpreted as judgements and some as logical propositions. When interpreting composite sentences, one may want to turn a judgemental interpretation or an ill-typed semantic interpretation into a proposition in order to obtain an intended semantics. For instance, an incorrect judgement $$a:A$$ may be turned into its propositional form $$\textsc {is}(A,a)$$ and an ill-typed application p(a) into $$\textsc {do}(p,a)$$, so that the propositional forms can take part in logical compositions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Intensional Formalization of Generic Statements.Hugolin Bergier - 2023 - Logica Universalis 17 (2):139-160.
    A statement is generic if it expresses a generalization about the members of a kind, as in, ’Pear trees blossom in May,’ or, ’Birds lay egg’. In classical logic, generic statements are formalized as universally quantified conditionals: ‘For all x, if..., then....’ We want to argue that such a logical interpretation fails to capture the intensional character of generic statements because it cannot express the generic statement as a simple proposition in Aristotle’s sense, i.e., a proposition containing only one single (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Identity in Martin‐Löf type theory.Ansten Klev - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 17 (2):e12805.
    The logic of identity contains riches not seen through the coarse lens of predicate logic. This is one of several lessons to draw from the subtle treatment of identity in Martin‐Löf type theory, to which the reader will be introduced in this article. After a brief general introduction we shall mainly be concerned with the distinction between identity propositions and identity judgements. These differ from each other both in logical form and in logical strength. Along the way, connections to philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Logical Analysis of the Anselm’s Unum Argumentum.Jean-Pierre Desclés - 2017 - Logica Universalis 11 (1):105-119.
    Anselm of Cantorbery wrote Proslogion, where is formulated the famous ‘Unum argumentum’ about the existence of God. This argument was been disputed and criticized by numerous logicians from an extensional view point. The classical predicate logic is not able to give a formal frame to develop an adequate analysis of this argument. According to us, this argument is not an ontological proof; it analyses the meaning of the “quo nihil maius cogitari posit”, a characterization of God, and establish, by absurd, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Algorithmic Iteration for Computational Intelligence.Giuseppe Primiero - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (3):521-543.
    Machine awareness is a disputed research topic, in some circles considered a crucial step in realising Artificial General Intelligence. Understanding what that is, under which conditions such feature could arise and how it can be controlled is still a matter of speculation. A more concrete object of theoretical analysis is algorithmic iteration for computational intelligence, intended as the theoretical and practical ability of algorithms to design other algorithms for actions aimed at solving well-specified tasks. We know this ability is already (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)The inconsistency of.M. W. Bunder - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (2):467-468.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equality in 21* with Restricted Subjects.M. W. Bunder - 1978 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 24 (8):125-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • G‐Stratification is Equivalent to F‐Stratification.C. B. Ben-Yelles - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (8-10):141-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lambda‐Calculus Models and Extensionality.R. Hindley & G. Longo - 1980 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 26 (19-21):289-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Explaining away Singular Non-existence Statements.Karel Lambert - 1963 - Dialogue 1 (4):381-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the unusual effectiveness of logic in computer science.Joseph Y. Halpern, Robert Harper, Neil Immerman, Phokion G. Kolaitis, Moshe Y. Vardi & Victor Vianu - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):213-236.
    In 1960, E. P. Wigner, a joint winner of the 1963 Nobel Prize for Physics, published a paper titled On the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences [61]. This paper can be construed as an examination and affirmation of Galileo's tenet that “The book of nature is written in the language of mathematics”. To this effect, Wigner presented a large number of examples that demonstrate the effectiveness of mathematics in accurately describing physical phenomena. Wigner viewed these examples as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Der prädikatenkalkül mit limitierten variablen grundlegung einer natürlichen exakten logik.Heinrich Behmann - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (2):112-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics.Sergei N. Artemov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):1-36.
    In 1933 Godel introduced a calculus of provability (also known as modal logic S4) and left open the question of its exact intended semantics. In this paper we give a solution to this problem. We find the logic LP of propositions and proofs and show that Godel's provability calculus is nothing but the forgetful projection of LP. This also achieves Godel's objective of defining intuitionistic propositional logic Int via classical proofs and provides a Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov style provability semantics for Int which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • Carnap’s Defense of Impredicative Definitions.Vera Flocke - 2019 - Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):372-404.
    A definition of a property P is impredicative if it quantifies over a domain to which P belongs. Due to influential arguments by Ramsey and Gödel, impredicative mathematics is often thought to possess special metaphysical commitments. It seems that an impredicative definition of a property P does not have the intended meaning unless P already exists, suggesting that the existence of P cannot depend on its explicit definition. Carnap (1937 [1934], p. 164) argues, however, that accepting impredicative definitions amounts to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Les représentations intermëdiaires.Jean-Pierre Desclés - 1990 - Revue de Synthèse 111 (1-2):33-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Completeness and Herbrand Theorems for Nominal Logic.James Cheney - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):299 - 320.
    Nominal logic is a variant of first-order logic in which abstract syntax with names and binding is formalized in terms of two basic operations: name-swapping and freshness. It relies on two important principles: equivariance (validity is preserved by name-swapping), and fresh name generation ("new" or fresh names can always be chosen). It is inspired by a particular class of models for abstract syntax trees involving names and binding, drawing on ideas from Fraenkel-Mostowski set theory: finite-support models in which each value (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plans, affordances, and combinatory grammar.Mark Steedman - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5):723-753.
    The idea that natural language grammar and planned action are relatedsystems has been implicit in psychological theory for more than acentury. However, formal theories in the two domains have tendedto look very different. This article argues that both faculties sharethe formal character of applicative systems based on operationscorresponding to the same two combinatory operations, namely functional composition and type-raising. Viewing them in thisway suggests simpler and more cognitively plausible accounts of bothsystems, and suggests that the language faculty evolved in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On adding (ξ) to weak equality in combinatory logic.Martin W. Bunder, J. Roger Hindley & Jonathan P. Seldin - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):590-607.
    Because the main difference between combinatory weak equality and λβ-equality is that the rule \begin{equation*}\tag{\xi} X = Y \vdash \lambda x.X = \lambda x.Y\end{equation*} is valid for the latter but not the former, it is easy to assume that another way of defining combinatory β-equality is to add rule (ξ) to the postulates for weak equality. However, to make this true, one must choose the definition of combinatory abstraction in (ξ) very carefully. If one tries to use one of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Types of I -free hereditary right maximal terms.Katalin Bimbó - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (5/6):607 - 620.
    The implicational fragment of the relevance logic "ticket entailment" is closely related to the so-called hereditary right maximal terms. I prove that the terms that need to be considered as inhabitants of the types which are theorems of $T_\rightarrow$ are in normal form and built in all but one casefrom B, B' and W only. As a tool in the proof ordered term rewriting systems are introduced. Based on the main theorem I define $FIT_\rightarrow$ - a Fitch-style calculus (related to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is reality fundamentally qualitative?Andrew Bacon - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (1):259-295.
    Individuals play a prominent role in many metaphysical theories. According to an individualistic metaphysics, reality is determined by the pattern of properties and relations that hold between individuals. A number of philosophers have recently brought to attention alternative views in which individuals do not play such a prominent role; in this paper I will investigate one of these alternatives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Introduction: History and Philosophy of Logical Notation.Francesco Bellucci, Amirouche Moktefi & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (1):1-2.
    We propose a reconstruction of the constellation of problems and philosophical positions on the nature and number of the primitives of logic in four authors of the nineteenth century logical scene: Peano, Padoa, Frege and Peirce. We argue that the proposed reconstruction forces us to recognize that it is in at least four different senses that a notation can be said to be simpler than another, and we trace the origins of these four senses in the writings of these authors. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simplex sigillum veri: Peano, Frege, and Peirce on the Primitives of Logic.Francesco Bellucci, Amirouche Moktefi & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (1):80-95.
    We propose a reconstruction of the constellation of problems and philosophical positions on the nature and number of the primitives of logic in four authors of the nineteenth century logical scene: Peano, Padoa, Frege and Peirce. We argue that the proposed reconstruction forces us to recognize that it is in at least four different senses that a notation can be said to be simpler than another, and we trace the origins of these four senses in the writings of these authors. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Functional Characters of Solvable Terms.M. Coppo, M. Dezani-Ciancaglini & B. Venneri - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (2-6):45-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Church-Rosser Property in Symmetric Combinatory Logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):536 - 556.
    Symmetic combinatory logic with the symmetric analogue of a combinatorially complete base (in the form of symmetric λ-calculus) is known to lack the Church-Rosser property. We prove a much stronger theorem that no symmetric combinatory logic that contains at least two proper symmetric combinators has the Church-Rosser property. Although the statement of the result looks similar to an earlier one concerning dual combinatory logic, the proof is different because symmetric combinators may form redexes in both left and right associated terms. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Positive logic and λ-constants.David Meredith - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (3):269 - 285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The church-Rosser property in dual combinatory logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (1):132-152.
    Dual combinators emerge from the aim of assigning formulas containing ← as types to combinators. This paper investigates formally some of the properties of combinatory systems that include both combinators and dual combinators. Although the addition of dual combinators to a combinatory system does not affect the unique decomposition of terms, it turns out that some terms might be redexes in two ways (with a combinator as its head, and with a dual combinator as its head). We prove a general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Combinatory Reductions and Lambda Reductions Compared.Roger Hindley - 1977 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 23 (7-12):169-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the formalization of semantic conventions.James G. Williams - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):220-243.
    This paper discusses six formalization techniques, of varying strengths, for extending a formal system based on traditional mathematical logic. The purpose of these formalization techniques is to simulate the introduction of new syntactic constructs, along with associated semantics for them. We show that certain techniques (among the six) subsume others. To illustrate sharpness, we also consider a selection of constructs and show which techniques can and cannot be used to introduce them. The six studied techniques were selected on the basis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A sequent calculus formulation of type assignment with equality rules for the \ambdaβ-calculus.Jonathan P. Seldin - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (4):643-649.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Combinatory logic with polymorphic types.William R. Stirton - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (3):317-343.
    Sections 1 through 4 define, in the usual inductive style, various classes of object including one which is called the “combinatory terms of polymorphic type”. Section 5 defines a reduction relation on these terms. Section 6 shows that the weak normalizability of the combinatory terms of polymorphic type entails the weak normalizability of the lambda terms of polymorphic type. The entailment is not vacuous, because the combinatory terms of polymorphic type are indeed weakly normalizable, as is proven in Sect. 7 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Montague's treatment of determiner phrases: A philosophical introduction.Ken Akiba - 2018 - Philosophy Compass 13 (6):e12496.
    This paper introduces Richard Montague's theory of determiner phrases to the philosophically oriented readers who are familiar with Russell's traditional treatment. Determiner phrases include not only quantifier phrases in the narrow sense, such as every man, some woman, and nothing, but also DP conjunctions such as Adam and Betty and Adam or Betty, and even proper names such as Adam and Betty. Montague treats all determiner phrases as belonging to type t, i.e., the type of functions from properties of individuals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The proper treatment of variables in predicate logic.Kai F. Wehmeier - 2018 - Linguistics and Philosophy 41 (2):209-249.
    In §93 of The Principles of Mathematics, Bertrand Russell observes that “the variable is a very complicated logical entity, by no means easy to analyze correctly”. This assessment is borne out by the fact that even now we have no fully satisfactory understanding of the role of variables in a compositional semantics for first-order logic. In standard Tarskian semantics, variables are treated as meaning-bearing entities; moreover, they serve as the basic building blocks of all meanings, which are constructed out of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Strong reduction and normal form in combinatory logic.Bruce Lercher - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):213-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A simple treatment of truth functions.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (4):301-302.
    In this note we present an axiomatization of the classical two-valued propositional calculus, for which proofs of decidability, consistency, completeness, and independence, are almost trivial (given an understanding of truth tables).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Abstract form of the church-rosser theorem. I.R. Hindley - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):545-560.
    One of the basic results in the theory of λ-conversion is the Church-Rosser Theorem, which says that, using certain rules for conversion and reduction of λ-formulae, any two interconvertible formulae can both be reduced to one formula. (I will not explain this in detail, as λ-conversion is described fully in Church's [2], where the Church-Rosser Theorem is Theorem 7 XXVII; see also Chapter 4 of Curry and Feys' [3].) The first part of the present paper contains an abstract form of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Extending the Curry-Howard interpretation to linear, relevant and other resource logics.Dov M. Gabbay & Ruy J. G. B. de Queiroz - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (4):1319-1365.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Some consistency proofs and a characterization of inconsistency proofs in illative combinatory logic.M. W. Bunder - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):89-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A complete and consistent modal set theory.Frederic B. Fitch - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (1):93-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Stratification and cut-elimination.Marcel Crabbé - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):213-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intensional logic in extensional language.Charles Parsons - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):289-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Alfred Tarski's work on general metamathematics.W. J. Blok & Don Pigozzi - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):36-50.
    In this essay we discuss Tarski's work on what he calledthe methodology of the deductive sciences, or more briefly, borrowing the terminology of Hilbert,metamathematics, The clearest statement of Tarski's views on this subject can be found in his textbookIntroduction to logic[41m].1Here he describes the tasks of metamathematics as “the detailed analysis and critical evaluation of the fundamental principles that are applied in the construction of logic and mathematics”. He goes on to describe what these fundamental principles are: All the expressions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logique mathématique et philosophie des mathématiques.Yvon Gauthier - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):243-275.
    Pour le philosophe intéressé aux structures et aux fondements du savoir théorétique, à la constitution d'une « méta-théorétique «, θεωρíα., qui, mieux que les « Wissenschaftslehre » fichtéenne ou husserlienne et par-delà les débris de la métaphysique, veut dans une intention nouvelle faire la synthèse du « théorétique », la logique mathématique se révèle un objet privilégié.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reducibilities in two models for combinatory logic.Luis E. Sanchis - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):221-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation