Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Science without reduction.Helmut F. Spinner - 1973 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-4):16 – 94.
    The aim of this essay is a criticism of reductionism ? both in its ?static? interpretation (usually referred to as the layer model or level?picture of science) and in its ?dynamic? interpretation (as a theory of the growth of scientific knowledge), with emphasis on the latter ? from the point of view of Popperian fallibilism and Feyerabendian pluralism, but without being committed to the idiosyncrasies of these standpoints. In both aspects of criticism, the rejection is based on the proposal of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In Praise of Clausius Entropy: Reassessing the Foundations of Boltzmannian Statistical Mechanics.Christopher Gregory Weaver - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (3):1-64.
    I will argue, pace a great many of my contemporaries, that there's something right about Boltzmann's attempt to ground the second law of thermodynamics in a suitably amended deterministic time-reversal invariant classical dynamics, and that in order to appreciate what's right about (what was at least at one time) Boltzmann's explanatory project, one has to fully apprehend the nature of microphysical causal structure, time-reversal invariance, and the relationship between Boltzmann entropy and the work of Rudolf Clausius.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Von L. Boltzmann bis J. J. Thomson: die Versuche einer mechanischen Grundlegung der Thermodynamik (1866?1890).Günter Bierhalter - 1992 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 44 (1):25-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Probability and statistics in Boltzmann's early papers on kinetic theory.Massimiliano Badino - unknown
    Boltzmann’s equilibrium theory has not received by the scholars the attention it deserves. It was always interpreted as a mere generalization of Maxwell’s work or, in the most favorable case, a sketch of some ideas more consistently developed in the 1872 memoir. In this paper, I try to prove that this view is ungenerous. My claim is that in the theory developed during the period 1866-1871 the generalization of Maxwell’s distribution was mainly a mean to get a more general scope: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zyklische Zeitvorstellung, Zeitrichtung und die frühen Versuche einer Deduktion des Zweiten Hauptsatzes der Thermodynamik.Von Günter Bierhalter - 1990 - Centaurus 33 (3):345-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An interpretation of macroscopic irreversibility within the Newtonian framework.Henry B. Hollinger & Michael J. Zenzen - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (3):309-354.
    Some of the most imaginative analyses in contemporary science have been fostered by the paradox of irreversibility. Rendered as a question the paradox reads: How can the anisotropic macrophysical behavior of a system of molecules be reconciled with the underlying reversible molecular model? Attempts to resolve and dissolve the paradox have appealed to large numbers of particles, jammed correlations, unseen perturbations, hidden variables or constraints, uncertainty principles, averaging procedures (e.g., coarse graining and time smoothing), stochastic flaws, cosmological origins, etc. While (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Das Hamiltonsche Prinzip und J. J. Thomsons Versuch einer mechanischen Grundlegung der Thermodynamik.Günter Bierhalter - 1993 - Centaurus 36 (2):102-116.
    AbstractenThis link goes to a English sectiondeThis link goes to a Deutsche sectionDie Mechanik ist ein Versuch, alle wahren Sätze, die wir zur Weltbeschreibung brauchen, nach einem Plane zu konstruieren. L. WITTGENSTEIN, Tractatus logico-philosophicus, Satz 6.343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark