Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Football is football and is interesting, very interesting.Paul Davis - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (2):140-152.
    There are robust consequences of the fact that football is football and not something else. The aesthetic personality of football does not submit to a template inappropriately borrowed from elsewhere. One consequence is that beauty should not be awarded privileged status. Any just aesthetics of the game must be properly hospitable to the game’s less hygienic and agonistic features, such as stolid defence, scuffling and scavenging, heroic goalkeeping, visible toil and strain, the intrinsic possibility of failure, the visibly strenuous working (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Good games and penalty shoot-outs.Emily Ryall - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (2):205-213.
    This paper considers the concept of a good game in terms of its relation to the fair testing of relevant skills and their aesthetic values. As such, it will consider what makes football ‘the beautiful game’ and what part penalty shoot-outs play, or should play, within it. It begins by outlining and refuting Kretchmar’s proposal that games which end following the elapsing of a set amount of time, such as football, are structurally, morally and aesthetically inferior to games which end (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Wasting Time.Mike McNamee - 2011 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 5 (1):1-3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Calling the beautiful game ugly: A response to Davis.Scott Kretchmar - 2008 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 2 (3):321 – 336.
    In a previous article (Kretchmar 2005), I identified problems in a certain species of games and traced these harms to something I called a 'game flaw'. Unfortunately, 'the beautiful game' is a member of that species. I say it is unfortunate because Paul Davis (2006), when taking me to task for providing an argument that, in his terms, was 'not especially compelling', focused on the game of soccer (hereafter, football). The issue over which we contended is one of 'time management'- (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • “A Games” and Their Relationship to T and E Games.R. Scott Kretchmar - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (1):47-57.
    In this essay, I revisit my claims about game structures and amend them by adding achievement-regulated games to previously analyzed time- and event-structured activities. In describing achievement formats, I discuss their heavy reliance on the world of work, their strong dependency on Suits’ lusory attitude, and their relative independence from constitutive rules. I argue that achievement-structured games carry disadvantages not shared by time- and event-regulated activities. I speculate that achievement gaming came first in our evolutionary history, but show that it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beyond Things: The Ontological Importance of Play According to Eugen Fink.Jan Halák - 2016 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 43 (2):199-214.
    Eugen Fink’s interpretation of play is virtually absent in the current philosophy of sport, despite the fact that it is rich in original descriptions of the structure of play. This might be due to Fink’s decision not to merely describe play, but to employ its analysis in the course of an elucidation of the ontological problem of the world as totality. On the other hand, this approach can enable us to properly evaluate the true existential and/or ontological value of play. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations