Switch to: References

Citations of:

Intentional systems

Journal of Philosophy 68 (February):87-106 (1971)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The hippocampus, synaptic enhancement, and intermediate-term memory.B. L. McNaughton & C. A. Barnes - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):507-508.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the hippocampus a store, intermediate or otherwise?Neil McNaughton - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):508-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beliefs, machines, and theories.John McCarthy - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):435-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Intentionality: Hardware, not software.Grover Maxwell - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):437-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Memory processing by the brain: Subregionalization, species-dependency, and network character.Hans J. Markowitsch - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):506-507.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Materialism, functionalism, and supervenient qualia.Ausonio Marras - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (3):475-92.
    Qualia are phenomenal properties of sensations and perceptual states: they are whatever it is that gives such states their “felt,” qualitative character. (In speaking of sensations, I speak of course not of mental objects or mental contents, but of mental events—of sensings, not sensa.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Do We Adopt the Intentional Stance Toward Humanoid Robots?Serena Marchesi, Davide Ghiglino, Francesca Ciardo, Jairo Perez-Osorio, Ebru Baykara & Agnieszka Wykowska - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Beyond different levels: embodiment and the developmental system.Peter J. Marshall - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial intelligence—the real thing?John C. Marshall - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):435-437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamic theories of behavior.Marc Mangel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The right stuff.J. Christopher Maloney - 1987 - Synthese 70 (March):349-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Three-store theories of memory.William S. Maki - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):505-506.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Actions, laws, and scientific psychology.John Macnamara, Vishwas P. Govitrikar & Brian Doan - 1988 - Cognition 29 (1):1-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The functionalist reply.William G. Lycan - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):434-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Epistemic value.William G. Lycan - 1985 - Synthese 64 (2):137 - 164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A deductive argument for the representational theory of thinking.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (3):404-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Deductive Argument for the Representational Theory of Thinking.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (3):404-420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Virtue, Self-Narratives, and the Causes of Action.David Lumsden & Joseph Ulatowski - forthcoming - Acta Analytica:1-16.
    Virtues can be considered to play a causal role in the production of behaviour and so too can our self-narratives. We identify a point of connection between the two cases and draw a parallel between them. But, those folk psychological notions, virtues and self-narratives, fail to reduce smoothly to the underlying human physiology. As a first step towards handling that failure to connect with the scientific framework that is the familiar grounding for our understanding of causation, we consider the causal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a theory of moods.Eric Lormand - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 47 (May):385-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Mental phenomena and behavior.B. Libet - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):434-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The Paradox of Charity.Marcin Lewiński - 2012 - Informal Logic 32 (4):403-439.
    The principle of charity is used in philosophy of language and argumentation theory as an important principle of interpretation which credits speakers with “the best” plausible interpretation of their discourse. I contend that the argumentation account, while broadly advocated, misses the basic point of a dialectical conception which approaches argumentation as discussion between two parties who disagree over the issue discussed. Therefore, paradoxically, an analyst who is charitable to one discussion party easily becomes uncharitable to the other. To overcome this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Speech Act Pluralism in Argumentative Polylogues.Marcin Lewinski - 2021 - Informal Logic 42 (4):421-451.
    I challenge two key assumptions of speech act theory, as applied to argumentation: illocutionary monism, grounded in the idea each utterance has only one (primary) illocutionary force, and the dyadic reduction, which models interaction as a dyadic affair between only two agents (speaker-hearer, proponentopponent). I show how major contributions to speech act inspired study of argumentation adhere to these assumptions even as illocutionary pluralism in argumentative polylogues is a significant empirical fact in need of theoretical attention. I demonstrate this with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Argumentation Theory Without Presumptions.Marcin Lewiński - 2017 - Argumentation 31 (3):591-613.
    In their extensive overview of various concepts of presumption Godden and Walton recognise “the heterogeneous picture of presumptions that exists in argumentation theory today”. I argue that this heterogeneity results from an epiphenomenal character of the notion of presumption. To this end, I first distinguish between three main classes of presumptions. Framework presumptions define the basic conditions of linguistic understanding and meaningful conversation. The “presumption of veracity” is their paradigm case. I argue that such presumptions are satisfactorily covered by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Must reasons be rational?Janet Levin - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (2):199-217.
    This paper challenges some leading views about the conditions under which the ascription of beliefs and desires can make sense of, or provide reasons for, a creature's behavior. I argue that it is unnecessary for behavior to proceed from beliefs and desires according to the principles of logic and decision theory, or even from principles that generally get things right. I also deny that it is necessary for behavior to proceed from principles that, though perhaps subrational, are similar to those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Collective Responsibility and the Individual.Joseph Levine - 2009 - Essays in Philosophy 10 (2):183-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the emotional character of trust.Bernd Lahno - 2001 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (2):171-189.
    Trustful interaction serves the interests of those involved. Thus, one could reason that trust itself may be analyzed as part of rational, goaloriented action. In contrast, common sense tells us that trust is an emotion and is, therefore, independent of rational deliberation to some extent. I will argue that we are right in trusting our common sense. My argument is conceptual in nature, referring to the common distinction between trust and pure reliance. An emotional attitude may be understood as some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The scientific study of lingustic behaviour: A perspective on the Skinner-Chomsky controversy.Hugh M. Lacey - 1974 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 4 (1):17–51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Does every theory have empirically equivalent rivals?André Kukla - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (2):137 - 166.
    The instrumentalist argument from the underdetermination of theories by data runs as follows: (1) every theory has empirically equivalent rivals; (2) the only warrant for believing one theory over another is its possession of a greater measure of empirical virtue; (3) therefore belief in any theory is arbitrary. In this paper, I examine the status of the first premise. Several arguments against the universal availability of empirically equivalent theoretical rivals are criticized, and four algorithms for producing empirically equivalent rivals are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Intentionality and Normativity.Uriah Kriegel - 2010 - Philosophical Issues 20 (1):185-208.
    One of the most enduring elements of Davidson’s legacy is the idea that intentionality is inherently normative. The normativity of intentionality means different things to different people and in different contexts, however. A subsidiary goal of this paper is to get clear on the sense in which Davidson means the thesis that intentionality is inherently normative. The central goal of the paper is to consider whether the thesis is true, in light of recent work on intentionality that insists on an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Peter Ludlow, ed., high noon on the electronic frontier: Conceptual issues in cyberspace. [REVIEW]David Koepsell - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (3):468-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations of the world: Memories, perceptions, beliefs, intentions, and plans.Paul Kockelman - 2006 - Semiotica 2006 (162):73-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can a Robot Lie? Exploring the Folk Concept of Lying as Applied to Artificial Agents.Markus Https://Orcidorg Kneer - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (10):e13032.
    The potential capacity for robots to deceive has received considerable attention recently. Many papers explore the technical possibility for a robot to engage in deception for beneficial purposes (e.g., in education or health). In this short experimental paper, I focus on a more paradigmatic case: robot lying (lying being the textbook example of deception) for nonbeneficial purposes as judged from the human point of view. More precisely, I present an empirical experiment that investigates the following three questions: (a) Are ordinary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Marr’s Computational Theory of Vision.Patricia Kitcher - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (March):1-24.
    David Marr's theory of vision has been widely cited by philosophers and psychologists. I have three projects in this paper. First, I try to offer a perspicuous characterization of Marr's theory. Next, I consider the implications of Marr's work for some currently popular philosophies of psychology, specifically, the "hegemony of neurophysiology view", the theories of Jerry Fodor, Daniel Dennett, and Stephen Stich, and the view that perception is permeated by belief. In the last section, I consider what the phenomenon of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Norms of behavior: Balancing generality with testability.George R. King & A. W. Logue - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sharpening the focus on functions of the hippocampus.Daniel P. Kimble - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):504-505.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructing Commitment: Brandom's Pragmatist Take on Rule‐Following.Matthias Kiesselbach - 2011 - Philosophical Investigations 35 (2):101-126.
    According to a standard criticism, Robert Brandom's “normative pragmatics”, i.e. his attempt to explain normative statuses in terms of practical attitudes, faces a dilemma. If practical attitudes and their interactions are specified in purely non-normative terms, then they underdetermine normative statuses; but if normative terms are allowed into the account, then the account becomes viciously circular. This paper argues that there is no dilemma, because the feared circularity is not vicious. While normative claims do exhibit their respective authors' practical attitudes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Non-reductive materialism and the spectrum of mind-body identity theories.Andrew Kernohan - 1988 - Dialogue 27 (3):475-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ontological status of computers or what is a computer?John Kelly - 1992 - AI and Society 6 (4):305-323.
    The development of computers as ‘mind tools’ has generated intriguing and provocative views about their potential human-like qualities. In this paper an attempt is made to explore the ‘real’ nature of computers by an examination of three widely different perspective, (1) the common-sense view of computers as tools; (2) the provocative view of computers as persons; and (3) the challenging view of computers as texts. In the course of the discussion an extended critique of the use of anthropomorphic terms in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More Brain Lesions: Kathleen V. Wilkes.Kathleen V. Wilkes - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (214):455 - 470.
    As philosophers of mind we seem to hold in common no very clear view about the relevance that work in psychology or the neurosciences may or may not have to our own favourite questions—even if we call the subject ‘philosophical psychology’. For example, in the literature we find articles on pain some of which do, some of which don't, rely more or less heavily on, for example, the work of Melzack and Wall; the puzzle cases used so extensively in discussions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Semantic control systems.Cliff Joslyn - 1995 - World Futures 45 (1):87-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Control of Perception and the Construction of Reality.Ernst von Glasersfeld John Richards - 1979 - Dialectica 33 (1):37-58.
    SummaryThis paper explicates a Constructivist Epistemology which underlies cybernetic models of perceiving and knowing. We focus on the recent work of W. T. Powers . Powers' model consists of hierarchially arranged negative feedback systems, is based on the claim that living organisms behave to control perceptions, and thus suggests that organisms construct their experiential world. We argue that this provides a basis for a modified scientific scepticism, a scepticism with a positive dimension gained by adding the notion of cognitive construction. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constitutional privacy.Jeffery L. Johnson - 1994 - Law and Philosophy 13 (2):161 - 193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the hippocampus, time, and interference.Leonard E. Jarrard - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):503-504.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Does our behavioral methodology conceal the deficit caused by hippocampal damage?David T. D. James - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):502-503.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coping with informational atomism - one of Jerry Fodor’s legacies.Pierre Jacob - 2020 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 11 (1):19-41.
    : Fodor was passionately unwilling to compromise. Of his several commitments, I focus here on informational atomism. Fodor staunchly rejected semantic holism for two conspiring reasons. He took it to threaten his commitment to the nomic character of psychological explanation. He also took it to pave the way towards relativism, which he found deeply offensive. In this paper, I reconstruct the strands of Fodor’s commitment to the computational version of the representational theory of mind that led him to informational atomism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The functional analysis of behaviour: Making room for Prufrock.Felicity A. Huntingford & Neil B. Metcalfe - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):137-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporal discontiguity: Alternative to, or component of, existing theories of hippocampal function?Donna J. Hughey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):501-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Does the Nation of China Think About Phenomenal States?Bryce Huebner, Michael Bruno & Hagop Sarkissian - 2010 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2):225-243.
    Critics of functionalism about the mind often rely on the intuition that collectivities cannot be conscious in motivating their positions. In this paper, we consider the merits of appealing to the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity. We demonstrate that collective mentality is not an affront to commonsense, and we report evidence that demonstrates that the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity is, to some extent, culturally specific rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • There's no such thing as a free lunch.Alasdair I. Houston & John M. McNamara - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):154-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of southern fundamentalism.Terence Horgan & George Graham - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 62 (May):107-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations