Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Stoics Against Stoics In Cudworth's A Treatise of Freewill.John Sellars - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5):935-952.
    In his A Treatise of Freewill, Ralph Cudworth argues against Stoic determinism by drawing on what he takes to be other concepts found in Stoicism, notably the claim that some things are ?up to us? and that these things are the product of our choice. These concepts are central to the late Stoic Epictetus and it appears at first glance as if Cudworth is opposing late Stoic voluntarism against early Stoic determinism. This paper argues that in fact, despite his claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Epictetus.Margaret Graver - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosopher, choisir sa vie. Du mythe d’Er à la prohairesis d’Épictète.Marion Bourbon - 2022 - Méthexis 34 (1):91-108.
    This paper aims to shed light on Plato’s myth of Er contribution to the emergence of a conception of choice as a principle of identity. Our hypothesis is that this myth brings out what is a real choice and that only philosophy enable us to make it. Philosophy as a way of life is that according to it our choice of life become a free choice and a principle of identity — because this first choice determines all the others in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La « prohairesis » chez Épictète :décision, volonté, ou « personne morale »?Jean-Baptiste Gourinat - 2005 - Philosophie Antique 5 (5):93-134.
    The notion of prohairesis is one of the key notions of Epictetus’ Stoicism. While this notion was of minor importance in ancient Stoicism, being a kind of impulse consis­ting of a « choice before a choice » and was rarely associated with a broader meaning (to the noteworthy exception of Diogenes of Seleucia), Epictetus borrowed from Aristotelian philosophy a notion of prohairesis as a preferential choice strictly bound to the notion of eph’ hemin (« what depends on us »). But (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Space for virtue in the economics of Kenneth J. Arrow, Amartya Sen and Elinor Ostrom.Dominic Burbidge - 2016 - Journal of Economic Methodology 23 (4):396-412.
    Virtue ethics interprets human action as pursuing good ends through practices that develop qualities internal to those final goals. The philosophical approach has been identified as critical of economics, leading in turn to the innovative response that by viewing the market as mutually beneficial exchange, economic practice is in fact defendable on virtue ethics grounds. This defends economics using arguments drawn from virtue ethics, but there is a need also to explore space for virtue ethics within economic theory. Examining key (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Exeinai und exousia. Ein frühes Kapitel aus der Geschichte der Freiheitsidee.Peter Stemmer - 2023 - Phronesis 68 (2):167-205.
    Exeinai bedeutet, dass es jemandem offensteht, eine bestimmte Handlung zu tun. Damit verbinden sich die Vorstellungen des Handlungsspielraums, des Anders-Könnens und des Anders-gekonnt-Habens wie auch die Vorstellung, selbst über sein Tun und Lassen bestimmen zu können. Exousia ist eng verknüpft mit eleutheria, Freiheit, und seit Aristoteles ist exeinai auch mit dem Begriff ep’ autō(i): etwas liegt bei einem, verbunden. Der Aufsatz bietet die erste detaillierte Untersuchung der Verwendung, der begrifflichen Verbindungen und der Signifikanz von exeinai und exousia. Damit fällt neues (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shaftesbury’s Distinctive Sentiments: Moral Sentiments and Self-Governance.Matthew J. Kisner - 2024 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 106 (3):548-575.
    This paper argues that Shaftesbury differs from other moral sentimentalists (Hutcheson, Hume, Smith) because he conceives of the moral sentiments as partial and first-personal, rather than impartial and spectatorial. This difference is grounded in Shaftesbury’s distinctive notion that moral self-governance consists in the self-examination of soliloquy. Breaking with his Stoic influences, Shaftesbury holds that the moral sentiments play the role of directing and guiding soliloquy. Because soliloquy is first-personal reflection that is directed to achieving happiness, claiming that the moral sentiments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark